Index [<< | >>]
First Part [<< | >>]
Question: 40 [<< | >>]
We now consider the persons in connection with the relations, or
properties; and there are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether relation is the same as person?
(2) Whether the relations distinguish and constitute the persons?
(3) Whether mental abstraction of the relations from the persons leaves
the hypostases distinct?
(4) Whether the relations, according to our mode of understanding,
presuppose the acts of the persons, or contrariwise?
Index [<< | >>]
First Part [<< | >>]
Question: 40 [<< | >>]
Article: 1 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that in God relation is not the same as person. For
when things are identical, if one is multiplied the others are
multiplied. But in one person there are several relations; as in the
person of the Father there is paternity and common spiration. Again, one
relation exists in two person, as common spiration in the Father and in
the Son. Therefore relation is not the same as person.
Objection 2: Further, according to the Philosopher (Phys. iv, text. 24),
nothing is contained by itself. But relation is in the person; nor can it
be said that this occurs because they are identical, for otherwise
relation would be also in the essence. Therefore relation, or property,
is not the same as person in God.
Objection 3: Further, when several things are identical, what is predicated of
one is predicated of the others. But all that is predicated of a Person
is not predicated of His property. For we say that the Father begets;
but not that the paternity is begetting. Therefore property is not the
same as person in God.
On the contrary, in God "what is" and "whereby it is" are the same,
according to Boethius (De Hebdom.). But the Father is Father by
paternity. In the same way, the other properties are the same as the
persons.
I answer that, Different opinions have been held on this point. Some
have said that the properties are not the persons, nor in the persons;
and these have thought thus owing to the mode of signification of the
relations, which do not indeed signify existence "in" something, but
rather existence "towards" something. Whence, they styled the relations
"assistant," as above explained (Question [28], Article [2]). But since relation,
considered as really existing in God, is the divine essence Itself, and
the essence is the same as person, as appears from what was said above
(Question [39], Article [1]), relation must necessarily be the same as person.
Others, therefore, considering this identity, said that the properties
were indeed the persons; but not "in" the persons; for, they said, there
are no properties in God except in our way of speaking, as stated above
(Question [32], Article [2]). We must, however, say that there are properties in God; as
we have shown (Question [32], Article [2]). These are designated by abstract terms,
being forms, as it were, of the persons. So, since the nature of a form
requires it to be "in" that of which it is the form, we must say that the
properties are in the persons, and yet that they are the persons; as we
say that the essence is in God, and yet is God.
Reply to Objection 1: Person and property are really the same, but differ in concept. Consequently, it does not follow that if one is multiplied, the other must also be multiplied. We must, however, consider that in God, by reason of the divine simplicity, a twofold real identity exists as regards what in creatures are distinct. For, since the divine simplicity excludes the composition of matter and form, it follows that in God the abstract is the same as the concrete, as "Godhead" and "God." And as the divine simplicity excludes the composition of subject and accident, it follows that whatever is attributed to God, is His essence Itself; and so, wisdom and power are the same in God, because they are both in the divine essence. According to this twofold identity, property in God is the same person. For personal properties are the same as the persons because the abstract and the concrete are the same in God; since they are the subsisting persons themselves, as paternity is the Father Himself, and filiation is the Son, and procession is the Holy Ghost. But the non-personal properties are the same as the persons according to the other reason of identity, whereby whatever is attributed to God is His own essence. Thus, common spiration is the same as the person of the Father, and the person of the Son; not that it is one self-subsisting person; but that as there is one essence in the two persons, so also there is one property in the two persons, as above explained (Question [30], Article [2]).
Reply to Objection 2: The properties are said to be in the essence, only by mode
of identity; but in the persons they exist by mode of identity, not
merely in reality, but also in the mode of signification; as the form
exists in its subject. Thus the properties determine and distinguish the
persons, but not the essence.
Reply to Objection 3: Notional participles and verbs signify the notional acts:
and acts belong to a "suppositum." Now, properties are not designated as
"supposita," but as forms of "supposita." And so their mode of
signification is against notional participles and verbs being predicated
of the properties.
Index [<< | >>]
First Part [<< | >>]
Question: 40 [<< | >>]
Article: 2 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that the persons are not distinguished by the
relations. For simple things are distinct by themselves. But the persons
are supremely simple. Therefore they are distinguished by themselves, and
not by the relation.
Objection 2: Further, a form is distinguished only in relation to its genus.
For white is distinguished from black only by quality. But "hypostasis"
signifies an individual in the genus of substance. Therefore the
hypostases cannot be distinguished by relations.
Objection 3: Further, what is absolute comes before what is relative. But the
distinction of the divine persons is the primary distinction. Therefore
the divine persons are not distinguished by the relations.
Objection 4: Further, whatever presupposes distinction cannot be the first
principle of distinction. But relation presupposes distinction, which
comes into its definition; for a relation is essentially what is towards
another. Therefore the first distinctive principle in God cannot be
relation.
On the contrary, Boethius says (De Trin.): "Relation alone multiplies
the Trinity of the divine persons."
I answer that, In whatever multitude of things is to be found something
common to all, it is necessary to seek out the principle of distinction.
So, as the three persons agree in the unity of essence, we must seek to
know the principle of distinction whereby they are several. Now, there
are two principles of difference between the divine persons, and these
are "origin" and "relation." Although these do not really differ, yet
they differ in the mode of signification; for "origin" is signified by
way of act, as "generation"; and "relation" by way of the form, as
"paternity."
Some, then, considering that relation follows upon act, have said that
the divine hypostases are distinguished by origin, so that we may say
that the Father is distinguished from the Son, inasmuch as the former
begets and the latter is begotten. Further, that the relations, or the
properties, make known the distinctions of the hypostases or persons as
resulting therefrom; as also in creatures the properties manifest the
distinctions of individuals, which distinctions are caused by the
material principles.
This opinion, however, cannot stand---for two reasons. Firstly, because,
in order that two things be understood as distinct, their distinction
must be understood as resulting from something intrinsic to both; thus in
things created it results from their matter or their form. Now origin of
a thing does not designate anything intrinsic, but means the way from
something, or to something; as generation signifies the way to a thing
generated, and as proceeding from the generator. Hence it is not possible
that what is generated and the generator should be distinguished by
generation alone; but in the generator and in the thing generated we must
presuppose whatever makes them to be distinguished from each other. In a
divine person there is nothing to presuppose but essence, and relation or
property. Whence, since the persons agree in essence, it only remains to
be said that the persons are distinguished from each other by the
relations. Secondly: because the distinction of the divine persons is not
to be so understood as if what is common to them all is divided, because
the common essence remains undivided; but the distinguishing principles
themselves must constitute the things which are distinct. Now the
relations or the properties distinguish or constitute the hypostases or
persons, inasmuch as they are themselves the subsisting persons; as
paternity is the Father, and filiation is the Son, because in God the
abstract and the concrete do not differ. But it is against the nature of
origin that it should constitute hypostasis or person. For origin taken
in an active sense signifies proceeding from a subsisting person, so that
it presupposes the latter; while in a passive sense origin, as
"nativity," signifies the way to a subsisting person, and as not yet
constituting the person.
It is therefore better to say that the persons or hypostases are
distinguished rather by relations than by origin. For, although in both
ways they are distinguished, nevertheless in our mode of understanding
they are distinguished chiefly and firstly by relations; whence this name
"Father" signifies not only a property, but also the hypostasis; whereas
this term "Begetter" or "Begetting" signifies property only; forasmuch as
this name "Father" signifies the relation which is distinctive and
constitutive of the hypostasis; and this term "Begetter" or "Begotten"
signifies the origin which is not distinctive and constitutive of the
hypostasis.
Reply to Objection 1: The persons are the subsisting relations themselves. Hence
it is not against the simplicity of the divine persons for them to be
distinguished by the relations.
Reply to Objection 2: The divine persons are not distinguished as regards being,
in which they subsist, nor in anything absolute, but only as regards
something relative. Hence relation suffices for their distinction.
Reply to Objection 3: The more prior a distinction is, the nearer it approaches
to unity; and so it must be the least possible distinction. So the
distinction of the persons must be by that which distinguishes the least
possible; and this is by relation.
Reply to Objection 4: Relation presupposes the distinction of the subjects, when
it is an accident; but when the relation is subsistent, it does not
presuppose, but brings about distinction. For when it is said that
relation is by nature to be towards another, the word "another" signifies
the correlative which is not prior, but simultaneous in the order of
nature.
Index [<< | >>]
First Part [<< | >>]
Question: 40 [<< | >>]
Article: 3 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that the hypostases remain if the properties or
relations are mentally abstracted from the persons. For that to which
something is added, may be understood when the addition is taken away; as
man is something added to animal which can be understood if rational be
taken away. But person is something added to hypostasis; for person is "a
hypostasis distinguished by a property of dignity." Therefore, if a
personal property be taken away from a person, the hypostasis remains.
Objection 2: Further, that the Father is Father, and that He is someone, are
not due to the same reason. For as He is the Father by paternity,
supposing He is some one by paternity, it would follow that the Son, in
Whom there is not paternity, would not be "someone." So when paternity is
mentally abstracted from the Father, He still remains "someone"---that
is, a hypostasis. Therefore, if property be removed from person, the
hypostasis remains.
Objection 3: Further, Augustine says (De Trin. v, 6): "Unbegotten is not the
same as Father; for if the Father had not begotten the Son, nothing would
prevent Him being called unbegotten." But if He had not begotten the Son,
there would be no paternity in Him. Therefore, if paternity be removed,
there still remains the hypostasis of the Father as unbegotten.
On the contrary, Hilary says (De Trin. iv): "The Son has nothing else
than birth." But He is Son by "birth." Therefore, if filiation be
removed, the Son's hypostasis no more remains; and the same holds as
regards the other persons.
I answer that, Abstraction by the intellect is twofold---when the
universal is abstracted from the particular, as animal abstracted from
man; and when the form is abstracted from the matter, as the form of a
circle is abstracted by the intellect from any sensible matter. The
difference between these two abstractions consists in the fact that in
the abstraction of the universal from the particular, that from which
the abstraction is made does not remain; for when the difference of
rationality is removed from man, the man no longer remains in the
intellect, but animal alone remains. But in the abstraction of the form
from the matter, both the form and the matter remain in the intellect;
as, for instance, if we abstract the form of a circle from brass, there
remains in our intellect separately the understanding both of a circle,
and of brass. Now, although there is no universal nor particular in God,
nor form and matter, in reality; nevertheless, as regards the mode of
signification there is a certain likeness of these things in God; and
thus Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii, 6) that "substance is common and
hypostasis is particular." So, if we speak of the abstraction of the
universal from the particular, the common universal essence remains in
the intellect if the properties are removed; but not the hypostasis of
the Father, which is, as it were, a particular.
But as regards the abstraction of the form from the matter, if the
non-personal properties are removed, then the idea of the hypostases and
persons remains; as, for instance, if the fact of the Father's being
unbegotten or spirating be mentally abstracted from the Father, the
Father's hypostasis or person remains.
If, however, the personal property be mentally abstracted, the idea of
the hypostasis no longer remains. For the personal properties are not to
be understood as added to the divine hypostases, as a form is added to a
pre-existing subject: but they carry with them their own "supposita,"
inasmuch as they are themselves subsisting persons; thus paternity is the
Father Himself. For hypostasis signifies something distinct in God, since
hypostasis means an individual substance. So, as relation distinguishes
and constitutes the hypostases, as above explained (Article [2]), it follows
that if the personal relations are mentally abstracted, the hypostases no
longer remain. Some, however, think, as above noted, that the divine
hypostases are not distinguished by the relations, but only by origin; so
that the Father is a hypostasis as not from another, and the Son is a
hypostasis as from another by generation. And that the consequent
relations which are to be regarded as properties of dignity, constitute
the notion of a person, and are thus called "personal properties." Hence,
if these relations are mentally abstracted, the hypostasis, but not the
persons, remain.
But this is impossible, for two reasons: first, because the relations
distinguish and constitute the hypostases, as shown above (Article [2]);
secondly, because every hypostasis of a rational nature is a person, as
appears from the definition of Boethius (De Duab. Nat.) that, "person is
the individual substance of a rational nature." Hence, to have hypostasis
and not person, it would be necessary to abstract the rationality from
the nature, but not the property from the person.
Reply to Objection 1: Person does not add to hypostasis a distinguishing property
absolutely, but a distinguishing property of dignity, all of which must
be taken as the difference. Now, this distinguishing property is one of
dignity precisely because it is understood as subsisting in a rational
nature. Hence, if the distinguishing property be removed from the person,
the hypostasis no longer remains; whereas it would remain were the
rationality of the nature removed; for both person and hypostasis are
individual substances. Consequently, in God the distinguishing relation
belongs essentially to both.
Reply to Objection 2: By paternity the Father is not only Father, but is a
person, and is "someone," or a hypostasis. It does not follow, however,
that the Son is not "someone" or a hypostasis; just as it does not follow
that He is not a person.
Reply to Objection 3: Augustine does not mean to say that the hypostasis of the
Father would remain as unbegotten, if His paternity were removed, as if
innascibility constituted and distinguished the hypostasis of the Father;
for this would be impossible, since "being unbegotten" says nothing
positive and is only a negation, as he himself says. But he speaks in a
general sense, forasmuch as not every unbegotten being is the Father. So,
if paternity be removed, the hypostasis of the Father does not remain in
God, as distinguished from the other persons, but only as distinguished
from creatures; as the Jews understand it.
Index [<< | >>]
First Part [<< | >>]
Question: 40 [<< | >>]
Article: 4 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that the notional acts are understood before the
properties. For the Master of the Sentences says (Sent. i, D, xxvii) that
"the Father always is, because He is ever begetting the Son." So it seems
that generation precedes paternity in the order of intelligence.
Objection 2: Further, in the order of intelligence every relation presupposes
that on which it is founded; as equality presupposes quantity. But
paternity is a relation founded on the action of generation. Therefore
paternity presupposes generation.
Objection 3: Further, active generation is to paternity as nativity is to
filiation. But filiation presupposes nativity; for the Son is so called
because He is born. Therefore paternity also presupposes generation.
On the contrary, Generation is the operation of the person of the
Father. But paternity constitutes the person of the Father. Therefore in
the order of intelligence, paternity is prior to generation.
I answer that, According to the opinion that the properties do not
distinguish and constitute the hypostases in God, but only manifest them
as already distinct and constituted, we must absolutely say that the
relations in our mode of understanding follow upon the notional acts, so
that we can say, without qualifying the phrase, that "because He begets,
He is the Father." A distinction, however, is needed if we suppose that
the relations distinguish and constitute the divine hypostases. For
origin has in God an active and passive signification---active, as
generation is attributed to the Father, and spiration, taken for the
notional act, is attributed to the Father and the Son; passive, as
nativity is attributed to the Son, and procession to the Holy Ghost. For,
in the order of intelligence, origin, in the passive sense, simply
precedes the personal properties of the person proceeding; because
origin, as passively understood, signifies the way to a person
constituted by the property. Likewise, origin signified actively is prior
in the order of intelligence to the non-personal relation of the person
originating; as the notional act of spiration precedes, in the order of
intelligence, the unnamed relative property common to the Father and the
Son. The personal property of the Father can be considered in a twofold
sense: firstly, as a relation; and thus again in the order of
intelligence it presupposes the notional act, for relation, as such, is
founded upon an act: secondly, according as it constitutes the person;
and thus the notional act presupposes the relation, as an action
presupposes a person acting.
Reply to Objection 1: When the Master says that "because He begets, He is
Father," the term "Father" is taken as meaning relation only, but not as
signifying the subsisting person; for then it would be necessary to say
conversely that because He is Father He begets.
Reply to Objection 2: This objection avails of paternity as a relation, but not
as constituting a person.
Reply to Objection 3: Nativity is the way to the person of the Son; and so, in
the order of intelligence, it precedes filiation, even as constituting
the person of the Son. But active generation signifies a proceeding from
the person of the Father; wherefore it presupposes the personal property
of the Father.