Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 35 [<< | >>]
After considering Christ's conception, we must treat of His nativity.
First, as to the nativity itself; secondly, as to His manifestation after
birth.
Concerning the first there are eight points of inquiry:
(1) Whether nativity regards the nature or the person?
(2) Whether another, besides His eternal, birth should be attributed to
Christ?
(3) Whether the Blessed Virgin is His Mother in respect of His temporal
birth?
(4) Whether she ought to be called the Mother of God?
(5) Whether Christ is the Son of God the Father and of the Virgin Mother
in respect of two filiations?
(6) Of the mode of the Nativity;
(7) Of its place;
(8) Of the time of the Nativity.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 35 [<< | >>]
Article: 1 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that nativity regards the nature rather than the
person. For Augustine [*Fulgentius] says (De Fide ad Petrum): "The
eternal Divine Nature could not be conceived and born of human nature,
except in a true human nature." Consequently it becomes the Divine Nature
to be conceived and born by reason of the human nature. Much more,
therefore, does it regard human nature itself.
Objection 2: Further, according to the Philosopher (Metaph. v), "nature" is so
denominated from "nativity." But things are denominated from one another
by reason of some likeness. Therefore it seems that nativity regards the
nature rather than the person.
Objection 3: Further, properly speaking, that is born which begins to exist by
nativity. But Christ's Person did not begin to exist by His nativity,
whereas His human nature did. Therefore it seems that the nativity
properly regards the nature, and not the person.
On the contrary, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii): "Nativity regards
the hypostasis, not the nature."
I answer that, Nativity can be attributed to someone in two ways: first,
as to its subject; secondly, as to its terminus. To him that is born it
is attributed as to its subject: and this, properly speaking, is the
hypostasis, not the nature. For since to be born is to be generated; as a
thing is generated in order for it to be, so is a thing born in order for
it to be. Now, to be, properly speaking, belongs to that which subsists;
since a form that does not subsist is said to be only inasmuch as by it
something is: and whereas person or hypostasis designates something as
subsisting, nature designates form, whereby something subsists.
Consequently, nativity is attributed to the person or hypostasis as to
the proper subject of being born, but not to the nature.
But to the nature nativity is attributed as to its terminus. For the
terminus of generation and of every nativity is the form. Now, nature
designates something as a form: wherefore nativity is said to be "the
road to nature," as the Philosopher states (Phys. ii): for the purpose of
nature is terminated in the form or nature of the species.
Reply to Objection 1: On account of the identity of nature and hypostasis in God,
nature fs sometimes put instead of person or hypostasis. And in this
sense Augustine says that the Divine Nature was conceived and born,
inasmuch as the Person of the Son was conceived and born in the human
nature.
Reply to Objection 2: No movement or change is denominated from the subject
moved, but from the terminus of the movement, whence the subject has its
species. For this reason nativity is not denominated from the person
born, but from nature, which is the terminus of nativity.
Reply to Objection 3: Nature, properly speaking, does not begin to exist: rather
is it the person that begins to exist in some nature. Because, as stated
above, nature designates that by which something is; whereas person
designates something as having subsistent being.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 35 [<< | >>]
Article: 2 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that temporal nativity is not to be attributed to
Christ. For "to be born is a certain movement of a thing that did not
exist before it was born, which movement procures for it the benefit of
existence" [*Cf. Augustine, De Unit. Trin. xii]. But Christ was from all
eternity. Therefore He could not be born in time.
Objection 2: Further, what is perfect in itself needs not to be born. But the
Person of the Son of God was perfect from eternity. Therefore He needs
not to be born in time. Therefore it seems that He had no temporal birth.
Objection 3: Further, properly speaking, nativity regards the person. But in
Christ there is only one person. Therefore in Christ there is but one
nativity.
Objection 4: Further, what is born by two nativities is born twice. But this
proposition is false; "Christ was born twice": because the nativity
whereby He was born of the Father suffers no interruption; since it is
eternal. Whereas interruption is required to warrant the use of the
adverb "twice": for a man is said to run twice whose running is
interrupted. Therefore it seems that we should not admit a double
nativity in Christ.
On the contrary, Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii): "We confess two
nativities in Christ: one of the Father---eternal; and one which occurred
in these latter times for our sake."
I answer that, As stated above (Article [1]), nature is compared to nativity,
as the terminus to movement or change. Now, movement is diversified
according to the diversity of its termini, as the Philosopher shows
(Phys. v). But, in Christ there is a twofold nature: one which He
received of the Father from eternity, the other which He received from
His Mother in time. Therefore we must needs attribute to Christ a twofold
nativity: one by which He was born of the Father from all eternity; one
by which He was born of His Mother in time.
Reply to Objection 1: This was the argument of a certain heretic, Felician, and
is solved thus by Augustine (Contra Felic. xii). "Let us suppose," says
he, "as many maintain, that in the world there is a universal soul,
which, by its ineffable movement, so gives life to all seed, that it is
not compounded with things begotten, but bestows life that they may be
begotten. Without doubt, when this soul reaches the womb, being intent on
fashioning the passible matter to its own purpose, it unites itself to
the personality thereof, though manifestly it is not of the same
substance; and thus of the active soul and passive matter, one man is
made out of two substances. And so we confess that the soul is born from
out the womb; but not as though, before birth, it was nothing at all in
itself. Thus, then, but in a way much more sublime, the Son of God was
born as man, just as the soul is held to be born together with the body:
not as though they both made one substance, but that from both, one
person results. Yet we do not say that the Son of God began thus to
exist: lest it be thought that His Divinity is temporal. Nor do we
acknowledge the flesh of the Son of God to have been from eternity: lest
it be thought that He took, not a true human body, but some resemblance
thereof."
Reply to Objection 2: This was an argument of Nestorius, and it is thus solved by
Cyril in an epistle [*Cf. Acta Concil. Ephes., p. 1, cap. viii]: "We do
not say that the Son of God had need, for His own sake, of a second
nativity, after that which is from the Father: for it is foolish and a
mark of ignorance to say that He who is from all eternity, and co-eternal
with the Father, needs to begin again to exist. But because for us and
for our salvation, uniting the human nature to His Person, He became the
child of a woman, for this reason do we say that He was born in the
flesh."
Reply to Objection 3: Nativity regards the person as its subject, the nature as
its terminus. Now, it is possible for several transformations to be in
the same subject: yet must they be diversified in respect of their
termini. But we do not say this as though the eternal nativity were a
transformation or a movement, but because it is designated by way of a
transformation or movement.
Reply to Objection 4: Christ can be said to have been born twice in respect of
His two nativities. For just as he is said to run twice who runs at two
different times, so can He be said to be born twice who is born once from
eternity and once in time: because eternity and time differ much more
than two different times, although each signifies a measure of duration.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 35 [<< | >>]
Article: 3 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that the Blessed Virgin cannot be called Christ's
Mother in respect of His temporal nativity. For, as stated above (Question [32], Article [4]), the Blessed Virgin Mary did not cooperate actively in begetting
Christ, but merely supplied the matter. But this does not seem sufficient
to make her His Mother: otherwise wood might be called the mother of the
bed or bench. Therefore it seems that the Blessed Virgin cannot be called
the Mother of Christ.
Objection 2: Further, Christ was born miraculously of the Blessed Virgin. But
a miraculous begetting does not suffice for motherhood or sonship: for we
do not speak of Eve as being the daughter of Adam. Therefore neither
should Christ be called the Son of the Blessed Virgin.
Objection 3: Further, motherhood seems to imply partial separation of the
semen. But, as Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii), "Christ's body was
formed, not by a seminal process, but by the operation of the Holy
Ghost." Therefore it seems that the Blessed Virgin should not be called
the Mother of Christ.
On the contrary, It is written (Mt. 1:18): "The generation of Christ was
in this wise. When His Mother Mary was espoused to Joseph," etc.
I answer that, The Blessed Virgin Mary is in truth and by nature the
Mother of Christ. For, as we have said above (Question [5], Article [2]; Question [31], Article [5]),
Christ's body was not brought down from heaven, as the heretic Valentine
maintained, but was taken from the Virgin Mother, and formed from her
purest blood. And this is all that is required for motherhood, as has
been made clear above (Question [31], Article [5]; Question [32], Article [4]). Therefore the Blessed
Virgin is truly Christ's Mother.
Reply to Objection 1: As stated above (Question [32], Article [3]), not every generation implies
fatherhood or motherhood and sonship, but only the generation of living
things. Consequently when inanimate things are made from some matter, the
relationship of motherhood and sonship does not follow from this, but
only in the generation of living things, which is properly called
nativity.
Reply to Objection 2: As Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii): "The temporal
nativity by which Christ was born for our salvation is, in a way,
natural, since a Man was born of a woman, and after the due lapse of time
from His conception: but it is also supernatural, because He was
begotten, not of seed, but of the Holy Ghost and the Blessed Virgin,
above the law of conception." Thus, then, on the part of the mother,
this nativity was natural, but on the part of the operation of the Holy
Ghost it was supernatural. Therefore the Blessed Virgin is the true and
natural Mother of Christ.
Reply to Objection 3: As stated above (Question [31], Article [5], ad 3; Question [32], Article [4]), the
resolution of the woman's semen is not necessary for conception; neither,
therefore, is it required for motherhood.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 35 [<< | >>]
Article: 4 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that the Blessed Virgin should not be called the
Mother of God. For in the Divine mysteries we should not make any
assertion that is not taken from Holy Scripture. But we read nowhere in
Holy Scripture that she is the mother or parent of God, but that she is
the "mother of Christ" or of "the Child," as may be seen from Mt. 1:18.
Therefore we should not say that the Blessed Virgin is the Mother of God.
Objection 2: Further, Christ is called God in respect of His Divine Nature.
But the Divine Nature did not first originate from the Virgin. Therefore
the Blessed Virgin should not be called the Mother of God.
Objection 3: Further, the word "God" is predicated in common of Father, Son,
and Holy Ghost. If, therefore, the Blessed Virgin is Mother of God it
seems to follow that she was the Mother of Father, Son, and Holy Ghost,
which cannot be allowed. Therefore the Blessed Virgin should not be
called Mother of God.
On the contrary, In the chapters of Cyril, approved in the Council of
Ephesus (P. 1, Cap. xxvi), we read: "If anyone confess not that the
Emmanuel is truly God, and that for this reason the Holy Virgin is the
Mother of God, since she begot of her flesh the Word of God made flesh,
let him be anathema."
I answer that, As stated above (Question [16], Article [1]), every word that signifies
a nature in the concrete can stand for any hypostasis of that nature.
Now, since the union of the Incarnation took place in the hypostasis, as
above stated (Question [2], Article [3]), it is manifest that this word "God" can stand
for the hypostasis, having a human and a Divine nature. Therefore
whatever belongs to the Divine and to the human nature can be attributed
to that Person: both when a word is employed to stand for it, signifying
the Divine Nature, and when a word is used signifying the human nature.
Now, conception and birth are attributed to the person and hypostasis in
respect of that nature in which it is conceived and born. Since,
therefore, the human nature was taken by the Divine Person in the very
beginning of the conception, as stated above (Question [33], Article [3]), it follows
that it can be truly said that God was conceived and born of the Virgin.
Now from this is a woman called a man's mother, that she conceived him
and gave birth to him. Therefore the Blessed Virgin is truly called the
Mother of God. For the only way in which it could be denied that the
Blessed Virgin is the Mother of God would be either if the humanity were
first subject to conception and birth, before this man were the Son of
God, as Photinus said; or if the humanity were not assumed unto unity of
the Person or hypostasis of the Word of God, as Nestorius maintained. But
both of these are erroneous. Therefore it is heretical to deny that the
Blessed Virgin is the Mother of God.
Reply to Objection 1: This was an argument of Nestorius, and it is solved by
saying that, although we do not find it said expressly in Scripture that
the Blessed Virgin is the Mother of God, yet we do find it expressly said
in Scripture that "Jesus Christ is true God," as may be seen 1 Jn. 5:20,
and that the Blessed Virgin is the "Mother of Jesus Christ," which is
clearly expressed Mt. 1:18. Therefore, from the words of Scripture it
follows of necessity that she is the Mother of God.
Again, it is written (Rm. 9:5) that Christ is of the Jews "according to
the flesh, who is over all things, God blessed for ever." But He is not
of the Jews except through the Blessed Virgin. Therefore He who is "above
all things, God blessed for ever," is truly born of the Blessed Virgin as
of His Mother.
Reply to Objection 2: This was an argument of Nestorius. But Cyril, in a letter
against Nestorius [*Cf. Acta Conc. Ephes., p. 1, cap. ii], answers it
thus: "Just as when a man's soul is born with its body, they are
considered as one being: and if anyone wish to say that the mother of the
flesh is not the mother of the soul, he says too much. Something like
this may be perceived in the generation of Christ. For the Word of God
was born of the substance of God the Father: but because He took flesh,
we must of necessity confess that in the flesh He was born of a woman."
Consequently we must say that the Blessed Virgin is called the Mother of
God, not as though she were the Mother of the Godhead, but because she is
the mother, according to His human nature, of the Person who has both the
divine and the human nature.
Reply to Objection 3: Although the name "God" is common to the three Persons, yet
sometimes it stands for the Person of the Father alone, sometimes only
for the Person of the Son or of the Holy Ghost, as stated above (Question [16], Article [1]; FP, Question [39], Article [4]). So that when we say, "The Blessed Virgin is the
Mother of God," this word "God" stands only for the incarnate Person of
the Son.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 35 [<< | >>]
Article: 5 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that there are two filiations in Christ. For
nativity is the cause of filiation. But in Christ there are two
nativities. Therefore in Christ there are also two filiations.
Objection 2: Further, filiation, which is said of a man as being the son of
someone, his father or his mother, depends, in a way, on him: because the
very being of a relation consists "in being referred to another";
wherefore if one of two relatives be destroyed, the other is destroyed
also. But the eternal filiation by which Christ is the Son of God the
Father depends not on His Mother, because nothing eternal depends on what
is temporal. Therefore Christ is not His Mother's Son by temporal
filiation. Either, therefore, He is not her Son at all, which is in
contradiction to what has been said above (Articles [3],4), or He must needs be
her Son by some other temporal filiation. Therefore in Christ there are
two filiations.
Objection 3: Further, one of two relatives enters the definition of the other;
hence it is clear that of two relatives, one is specified from the other.
But one and the same cannot be in diverse species. Therefore it seems
impossible that one and the same relation be referred to extremes which
are altogether diverse. But Christ is said to be the Son of the Eternal
Father and a temporal mother, who are terms altogether diverse. Therefore
it seems that Christ cannot, by the same relation, be called the Son of
the Father and of His Mother Therefore in Christ there are two filiations.
On the contrary, As Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii), things
pertaining to the nature are multiple in Christ; but not those things
that pertain to the Person. But filiation belongs especially to the
Person, since it is a personal property, as appears from what was said in
the FP, Question [32], Article [3]; FP, Question [40], Article [2]. Therefore there is but one
filiation in Christ.
I answer that, opinions differ on this question. For some, considering only the cause of filiation, which is nativity, put two filiations in Christ, just as there are two nativities. On the contrary, others, considering only the subject of filiation, which is the person or hypostasis, put only one filiation in Christ, just as there is but one hypostasis or person. Because the unity or plurality of a relation is considered in respect, not of its terms, but of its cause or of its subject. For if it were considered in respect of its terms, every man would of necessity have in himself two filiations---one in reference to his father, and another in reference to his mother. But if we consider the question aright, we shall see that every man bears but one relation to both his father and his mother, on account of the unity of the cause thereof. For man is born by one birth of both father and mother: whence he bears but one relation to both. The same is said of one master who teaches many disciples the same doctrine, and of one lord who governs many subjects by the same power. But if there be various causes specifically diverse, it seems that in consequence the relations differ in species: wherefore nothing hinders several such relations being in the same subject. Thus if a man teach grammar to some and logic to others, his teaching is of a different kind in one case and in the other; and therefore one and the same man may have different relations as the master of different disciples, or of the same disciples in regard to diverse doctrines. Sometimes, however, it happens that a man bears a relation to several in respect of various causes, but of the same species: thus a father may have several sons by several acts of generation. Wherefore the
paternity cannot differ specifically, since the acts of generation are
specifically the same. And because several forms of the same species
cannot at the same time be in the same subject, it is impossible for
several paternities to be in a man who is the father of several sons by
natural generation. But it would not be so were he the father of one son
by natural generation and of another by adoption.
Now, it is manifest that Christ was not born by one and the same
nativity, of the Father from eternity, and of His Mother in time: indeed,
these two nativities differ specifically. Wherefore, as to this, we must
say that there are various filiations, one temporal and the other
eternal. Since, however, the subject of filiation is neither the nature
nor part of the nature, but the person or hypostasis alone; and since in
Christ there is no other hypostasis or person than the eternal, there can
be no other filiation in Christ but that which is in the eternal
hypostasis. Now, every relation which is predicated of God from time does
not put something real in the eternal God, but only something according
to our way of thinking, as we have said in the FP, Question [13], Article [7]. Therefore
the filiation by which Christ is referred to His Mother cannot be a real
relation, but only a relation of reason.
Consequently each opinion is true to a certain extent. For if we
consider the adequate causes of filiation, we must needs say that there
are two filiations in respect of the twofold nativity. But if we consider
the subject of filiation, which can only be the eternal suppositum, then
no other than the eternal filiation in Christ is a real relation.
Nevertheless, He has the relation of Son in regard to His Mother, because
it is implied in the relation of motherhood to Christ. Thus God is called
Lord by a relation which is implied in the real relation by which the
creature is subject to God. And although lordship is not a real relation
in God, yet is He really Lord through the real subjection of the creature
to Him. In the same way Christ is really the Son of the Virgin Mother
through the real relation of her motherhood to Christ.
Reply to Objection 1: Temporal nativity would cause a real temporal filiation in
Christ if there were in Him a subject capable of such filiation. But this
cannot be; since the eternal suppositum cannot be receptive of a temporal
relation, as stated above. Nor can it be said that it is receptive of
temporal filiation by reason of the human nature, just as it is receptive
of the temporal nativity; because human nature would need in some way to
be the subject of filiation, just as in a way it is the subject of
nativity; for since an Ethiopian is said to be white by reason of his
teeth, it must be that his teeth are the subject of whiteness. But human
nature can nowise be the subject of filiation, because this relation
regards directly the person.
Reply to Objection 2: Eternal filiation does not depend on a temporal mother, but together with this eternal filiation we understand a certain temporal relation dependent on the mother, in respect of which relation Christ is called the Son of His Mother.
Reply to Objection 3: One and being are mutually consequent, as is said Metaph.
iv. Therefore, just as it happens that in one of the extremes of a
relation there is something real, whereas in the other there is not
something real, but merely a certain aspect, as the Philosopher observes
of knowledge and the thing known; so also it happens that on the part of
one extreme there is one relation, whereas on the part of the other there
are many. Thus in man on the part of his parents there is a twofold
relation, the one of paternity, the other of motherhood, which are
specifically diverse, inasmuch as the father is the principle of
generation in one way, and the mother in another (whereas if many be the
principle of one action and in the same way---for instance, if many.
together draw a ship along---there would be one and the same relation in
all of them); but on the part of the child there is but one filiation in
reality, though there be two in aspect, corresponding to the two
relations in the parents, as considered by the intellect. And thus in one
way there is only one real filiation in Christ, which is in respect of
the Eternal Father: yet there is another temporal relation in regard to
His temporal mother.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 35 [<< | >>]
Article: 6 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that Christ was not born without His Mother
suffering. For just as man's death was a result of the sin of our first
parents, according to Gn. 2:17: "In what day soever ye shall eat, ye
shall [Vulg.: 'thou shalt eat of it, thou shalt] die"; so were the pains
of childbirth, according to Gn. 3:16: "In sorrow shalt thou bring forth
children." But Christ was willing to undergo death. Therefore for the
same reason it seems that His birth should have been with pain.
Objection 2: Further, the end is proportionate to the beginning. But Christ
ended His life in pain, according to Is. 53:4: "Surely . . . He hath
carried our sorrows." Therefore it seems that His nativity was not
without the pains of childbirth.
Objection 3: Further, in the book on the birth of our Saviour [*Protevangelium
Jacobi xix, xx] it is related that midwives were present at Christ's
birth; and they would be wanted by reason of the mother's suffering pain.
Therefore it seems that the Blessed Virgin suffered pain in giving birth
to her Child.
On the contrary, Augustine says (Serm. de Nativ. [*Supposititious]),
addressing himself to the Virgin-Mother: "In conceiving thou wast all
pure, in giving birth thou wast without pain."
I answer that, The pains of childbirth are caused by the infant opening
the passage from the womb. Now it has been said above (Question [28], Article [2], Replies to objections), that Christ came forth from the closed womb of
His Mother, and, consequently, without opening the passage. Consequently
there was no pain in that birth, as neither was there any corruption; on
the contrary, there was much joy therein for that God-Man "was born into
the world," according to Is. 35:1,2: "Like the lily, it shall bud forth
and blossom, and shall rejoice with joy and praise."
Reply to Objection 1: The pains of childbirth in the woman follow from the
mingling of the sexes. Wherefore (Gn. 3:16) after the words, "in sorrow
shalt thou bring forth children," the following are added: "and thou
shalt be under thy husband's power." But, as Augustine says (Serm. de
Assumpt. B. Virg., [*Supposititious]), from this sentence we must exclude
the Virgin-Mother of God; who, "because she conceived Christ without the
defilement of sin, and without the stain of sexual mingling, therefore
did she bring Him forth without pain, without violation of her virginal
integrity, without detriment to the purity of her maidenhood." Christ,
indeed, suffered death, but through His own spontaneous desire, in order
to atone for us, not as a necessary result of that sentence, for He was
not a debtor unto death.
Reply to Objection 2: As "by His death" Christ "destroyed our death" [*Preface of
the Mass in Paschal-time], so by His pains He freed us from our pains;
and so He wished to die a painful death. But the mother's pains in
childbirth did not concern Christ, who came to atone for our sins. And
therefore there was no need for His Mother to suffer in giving birth.
Reply to Objection 3: We are told (Lk. 2:7) that the Blessed Virgin herself
"wrapped up in swaddling clothes" the Child whom she had brought forth,
"and laid Him in a manger." Consequently the narrative of this book,
which is apocryphal, is untrue. Wherefore Jerome says (Adv. Helvid. iv):
"No midwife was there, no officious women interfered. She was both mother
and midwife. 'With swaddling clothes,' says he, 'she wrapped up the
child, and laid Him in a manger.'" These words prove the falseness of the
apocryphal ravings.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 35 [<< | >>]
Article: 7 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that Christ should not have been born in Bethlehem.
For it is written (Is. 2:3): "The law shall come forth from Sion, and the
Word of the Lord from Jerusalem." But Christ is truly the Word of God.
Therefore He should have come into the world at Jerusalem.
Objection 2: Further, it is said (Mt. 2:23) that it is written of Christ that
"He shall be called a Nazarene"; which is taken from Is. 11:1: "A flower
shall rise up out of his root"; for "Nazareth" is interpreted "a flower."
But a man is named especially from the place of his birth. Therefore it
seems that He should have been born in Nazareth, where also He was
conceived and brought up.
Objection 3: Further, for this was our Lord born into the world, that He might
make known the true faith. according to Jn. 18:37: "For this was I born,
and for this came I into the world; that I should give testimony to the
truth." But this would have been easier if He had been born in the city
of Rome, which at that time ruled the world; whence Paul, writing to the
Romans (1:8) says: "Your faith is spoken of in the whole world."
Therefore it seems that He should not have been born in Bethlehem.
On the contrary, It is written (Mich. 5:2): "And thou, Bethlehem,
Ephrata . . . out of thee shall He come forth unto Me, that is to be the
ruler in Israel."
I answer that, Christ willed to be born in Bethlehem for two reasons.
First, because "He was made . . . of the seed of David according to the
flesh," as it is written (Rm. 1:3); to whom also was a special promise
made concerning Christ; according to 2 Kgs. 23:1: "The man to whom it was
appointed concerning the Christ of the God of Jacob . . . said."
Therefore He willed to be born at Bethlehem, where David was born, in
order that by the very birthplace the promise made to David might be
shown to be fulfilled. The Evangelist points this out by saying: "Because
He was of the house and of the family of David." Secondly, because, as
Gregory says (Hom. viii in Evang.): "Bethlehem is interpreted 'the house
of bread.' It is Christ Himself who said, 'I am the living Bread which
came down from heaven.'"
Reply to Objection 1: As David was born in Bethlehem, so also did he choose
Jerusalem to set up his throne there, and to build there the Temple of
God, so that Jerusalem was at the same time a royal and a priestly city.
Now, Christ's priesthood and kingdom were "consummated" principally in
His Passion. Therefore it was becoming that He should choose Bethlehem
for His Birthplace and Jerusalem for the scene of His Passion.
At the same time, too, He put to silence the vain boasting of men who
take pride in being born in great cities, where also they desire
especially to receive honor. Christ, on the contrary, willed to be born
in a mean city, and to suffer reproach in a great city.
Reply to Objection 2: Christ wished "to flower" by His holy life, not in His
carnal birth. Therefore He wished to be fostered and brought up at
Nazareth. But He wished to be born at Bethlehem away from home; because,
as Gregory says (Hom. viii in Evang.), through the human nature which He
had taken, He was born, as it were, in a foreign place---foreign not to
His power, but to His Nature. And, again, as Bede says on Lk. 2:7: "In
order that He who found no room at the inn might prepare many mansions
for us in His Father's house."
Reply to Objection 3: According to a sermon in the Council of Ephesus [*P. iii,
cap. ix]: "If He had chosen the great city of Rome, the change in the
world would be ascribed to the influence of her citizens. If He had been
the son of the Emperor, His benefits would have been attributed to the
latter's power. But that we might acknowledge the work of God in the
transformation of the whole earth, He chose a poor mother and a
birthplace poorer still."
"But the weak things of the world hath God chosen, that He may confound
the strong" (1 Cor. 1:27). And therefore, in order the more to show His
power, He set up the head of His Church in Rome itself, which was the
head of the world, in sign of His complete victory, in order that from
that city the faith might spread throughout the world; according to Is.
26:5,6: "The high city He shall lay low . . . the feet of the poor," i.e.
of Christ, "shall tread it down; the steps of the needy," i.e. of the
apostles Peter and Paul.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 35 [<< | >>]
Article: 8 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that Christ was not born at a fitting time. Because
Christ came in order to restore liberty to His own. But He was born at a
time of subjection---namely, when the whole world, as it were, tributary
to Augustus, was being enrolled, at his command as Luke relates (2:1).
Therefore it seems that Christ was not born at a fitting time.
Objection 2: Further, the promises concerning the coming of Christ were not
made to the Gentiles; according to Rm. 9:4: "To whom belong . . . the
promises." But Christ was born during the reign of a foreigner, as
appears from Mt. 2:1: "When Jesus was born in the days of King Herod."
Therefore it seems that He was not born at a fitting time.
Objection 3: Further, the time of Christ's presence on earth is compared to
the day, because He is the "Light of the world"; wherefore He says
Himself (Jn. 9:4): "I must work the works of Him that sent Me, whilst it
is day." But in summer the days are longer than in winter. Therefore,
since He was born in the depth of winter, eight days before the Kalends
of January, it seems that He was not born at a fitting time.
On the contrary, It is written (Gal. 4:4): "When the fulness of the time
was come, God sent His Son, made of a woman, made under the law."
I answer that, There is this difference between Christ and other men,
that, whereas they are born subject to the restrictions of time, Christ,
as Lord and Maker of all time, chose a time in which to be born, just as
He chose a mother and a birthplace. And since "what is of God is well
ordered" and becomingly arranged, it follows that Christ was born at a
most fitting time.
Reply to Objection 1: Christ came in order to bring us back from a state of
bondage to a state of liberty. And therefore, as He took our mortal
nature in order to restore us to life, so, as Bede says (Super Luc. ii,
4,5), "He deigned to take flesh at such a time that, shortly after His
birth, He would be enrolled in Caesar's census, and thus submit Himself
to bondage for the sake of our liberty."
Moreover, at that time, when the whole world lived under one ruler,
peace abounded on the earth. Therefore it was a fitting time for the
birth of Christ, for "He is our peace, who hath made both one," as it is
written (Eph. 2:14). Wherefore Jerome says on Is. 2:4: "If we search the
page of ancient history, we shall find that throughout the whole world
there was discord until the twenty-eighth year of Augustus Caesar: but
when our Lord was born, all war ceased"; according to Is. 2:4: "Nation
shall not lift up sword against nation."
Again, it was fitting that Christ should be born while the world was
governed by one ruler, because "He came to gather His own [Vulg.: 'the
children of God'] together in one" (Jn. 11:52), that there might be "one
fold and one shepherd" (Jn. 10:16).
Reply to Objection 2: Christ wished to be born during the reign of a foreigner,
that the prophecy of Jacob might be fulfilled (Gn. 49:10): "The sceptre
shall not be taken away from Juda, nor a ruler from his thigh, till He
come that is to be sent." Because, as Chrysostom says (Hom. ii in Matth.
[*Opus Imperf., falsely ascribed to Chrysostom]), as long as the Jewish
"people was governed by Jewish kings, however wicked, prophets were sent
for their healing. But now that the Law of God is under the power of a
wicked king, Christ is born; because a grave and hopeless disease
demanded a more skilful physician."
Reply to Objection 3: As says the author of the book De Qq. Nov. et Vet. Test.,
"Christ wished to be born, when the light of day begins to increase in
length," so as to show that He came in order that man might come nearer
to the Divine Light, according to Lk. 1:79: "To enlighten them that sit
in darkness and in the shadow of death."
In like manner He chose to be born in the rough winter season, that He
might begin from then to suffer in body for us.