Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
In due sequence we must consider the contrary vices: first, unbelief,
which is contrary to faith; secondly, blasphemy, which is opposed to
confession of faith; thirdly, ignorance and dulness of mind, which are
contrary to knowledge and understanding.
As to the first, we must consider (1) unbelief in general; (2) heresy;
(3) apostasy from the faith.
Under the first head there are twelve points of inquiry:
(1) Whether unbelief is a sin?
(2) What is its subject?
(3) Whether it is the greatest of sins?
(4) Whether every action of unbelievers is a sin?
(5) Of the species of unbelief;
(6) Of their comparison, one with another;
(7) Whether we ought to dispute about faith with unbelievers?
(8) Whether they ought to be compelled to the faith?
(9) Whether we ought to have communications with them?
(10) Whether unbelievers can have authority over Christians?
(11) Whether the rites of unbelievers should be tolerated?
(12) Whether the children of unbelievers are to be baptized against
their parents' will?
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 1 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that unbelief is not a sin. For every sin is
contrary to nature, as Damascene proves (De Fide Orth. ii, 4). Now
unbelief seems not to be contrary to nature; for Augustine says (De
Praedest. Sanct. v) that "to be capable to having faith, just as to be
capable of having charity, is natural to all men; whereas to have faith,
even as to have charity, belongs to the grace of the faithful."
Therefore not to have faith, which is to be an unbeliever, is not a sin.
Objection 2: Further, no one sins that which he cannot avoid, since every sin
is voluntary. Now it is not in a man's power to avoid unbelief, for he
cannot avoid it unless he have faith, because the Apostle says (Rm. 10:14): "How shall they believe in Him, of Whom they have not heard? And
how shall they hear without a preacher?" Therefore unbelief does not seem
to be a sin.
Objection 3: Further, as stated above (FS, Question [84], Article [4]), there are seven
capital sins, to which all sins are reduced. But unbelief does not seem
to be comprised under any of them. Therefore unbelief is not a sin.
On the contrary, Vice is opposed to virtue. Now faith is a virtue, and
unbelief is opposed to it. Therefore unbelief is a sin.
I answer that, Unbelief may be taken in two ways: first, by way of pure
negation, so that a man be called an unbeliever, merely because he has
not the faith. Secondly, unbelief may be taken by way of opposition to
the faith; in which sense a man refuses to hear the faith, or despises
it, according to Is. 53:1: "Who hath believed our report?" It is this
that completes the notion of unbelief, and it is in this sense that
unbelief is a sin.
If, however, we take it by way of pure negation, as we find it in those
who have heard nothing about the faith, it bears the character, not of
sin, but of punishment, because such like ignorance of Divine things is a
result of the sin of our first parent. If such like unbelievers are
damned, it is on account of other sins, which cannot be taken away
without faith, but not on account of their sin of unbelief. Hence Our
Lord said (Jn. 15:22) "If I had not come, and spoken to them, they would
not have sin"; which Augustine expounds (Tract. lxxxix in Joan.) as
"referring to the sin whereby they believed not in Christ."
Reply to Objection 1: To have the faith is not part of human nature, but it is
part of human nature that man's mind should not thwart his inner
instinct, and the outward preaching of the truth. Hence, in this way,
unbelief is contrary to nature.
Reply to Objection 2: This argument takes unbelief as denoting a pure negation.
Reply to Objection 3: Unbelief, in so far as it is a sin, arises from pride,
through which man is unwilling to subject his intellect to the rules of
faith, and to the sound interpretation of the Fathers. Hence Gregory says
(Moral. xxxi, 45) that "presumptuous innovations arise from vainglory."
It might also be replied that just as the theological virtues are not
reduced to the cardinal virtues, but precede them, so too, the vices
opposed to the theological virtues are not reduced to the capital vices.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 2 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that unbelief is not in the intellect as its
subject. For every sin is in the will, according to Augustine (De Duabus
Anim. x, xi). Now unbelief is a sin, as stated above (Article [1]). Therefore
unbelief resides in the will and not in the intellect.
Objection 2: Further, unbelief is sinful through contempt of the preaching of
the faith. But contempt pertains to the will. Therefore unbelief is in
the will.
Objection 3: Further, a gloss [*Augustine, Enchiridion lx.] on 2 Cor. 11:14
"Satan . . . transformeth himself into an angel of light," says that if
"a wicked angel pretend to be a good angel, and be taken for a good
angel, it is not a dangerous or an unhealthy error, if he does or says
what is becoming to a good angel." This seems to be because of the
rectitude of the will of the man who adheres to the angel, since his
intention is to adhere to a good angel. Therefore the sin of unbelief
seems to consist entirely in a perverse will: and, consequently, it does
not reside in the intellect.
On the contrary, Things which are contrary to one another are in the
same subject. Now faith, to which unbelief is opposed, resides in the
intellect. Therefore unbelief also is in the intellect.
I answer that, As stated above (FS, Question [74], Articles [1],2), sin is said to be
in the power which is the principle of the sinful act. Now a sinful act
may have two principles: one is its first and universal principle, which
commands all acts of sin; and this is the will, because every sin is
voluntary. The other principle of the sinful act is the proper and
proximate principle which elicits the sinful act: thus the concupiscible
is the principle of gluttony and lust, wherefore these sins are said to
be in the concupiscible. Now dissent, which is the act proper to
unbelief, is an act of the intellect, moved, however, by the will, just
as assent is.
Therefore unbelief, like faith, is in the intellect as its proximate
subject. But it is in the will as its first moving principle, in which
way every sin is said to be in the will.
Hence the Reply to the First Objection is clear.
Reply to Objection 2: The will's contempt causes the intellect's dissent, which
completes the notion of unbelief. Hence the cause of unbelief is in the
will, while unbelief itself is in the intellect.
Reply to Objection 3: He that believes a wicked angel to be a good one, does not
dissent from a matter of faith, because "his bodily senses are deceived,
while his mind does not depart from a true and right judgment" as the
gloss observes [*Augustine, Enchiridion lx]. But, according to the same
authority, to adhere to Satan when he begins to invite one to his abode,
i.e. wickedness and error, is not without sin.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 3 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that unbelief is not the greatest of sins. For
Augustine says (De Bapt. contra Donat. iv, 20): "I should hesitate to
decide whether a very wicked Catholic ought to be preferred to a heretic,
in whose life one finds nothing reprehensible beyond the fact that he is
a heretic." But a heretic is an unbeliever. Therefore we ought not to say
absolutely that unbelief is the greatest of sins.
Objection 2: Further, that which diminishes or excuses a sin is not,
seemingly, the greatest of sins. Now unbelief excuses or diminishes sin:
for the Apostle says (1 Tim. 1:12,13): "I . . . before was a blasphemer,
and a persecutor and contumelious; but I obtained . . . mercy . . .
because I did it ignorantly in unbelief." Therefore unbelief is not the
greatest of sins.
Objection 3: Further, the greater sin deserves the greater punishment,
according to Dt. 25:2: "According to the measure of the sin shall the
measure also of the stripes be." Now a greater punishment is due to
believers than to unbelievers, according to Heb. 10:29: "How much more,
do you think, he deserveth worse punishments, who hath trodden under foot
the Son of God, and hath esteemed the blood of the testament unclean, by
which he was sanctified?" Therefore unbelief is not the greatest of sins.
On the contrary, Augustine, commenting on Jn. 15:22, "If I had not come,
and spoken to them, they would not have sin," says (Tract. lxxxix in
Joan.): "Under the general name, He refers to a singularly great sin. For
this," viz. infidelity, "is the sin to which all others may be traced."
Therefore unbelief is the greatest of sins.
I answer that, Every sin consists formally in aversion from God, as
stated above (FS, Question [71], Article [6]; FS, Question [73], Article [3]). Hence the more a sin
severs man from God, the graver it is. Now man is more than ever
separated from God by unbelief, because he has not even true knowledge of
God: and by false knowledge of God, man does not approach Him, but is
severed from Him.
Nor is it possible for one who has a false opinion of God, to know Him
in any way at all, because the object of his opinion is not God.
Therefore it is clear that the sin of unbelief is greater than any sin
that occurs in the perversion of morals. This does not apply to the sins
that are opposed to the theological virtues, as we shall stated further
on (Question [20], Article [3]; Question [34], Article [2], ad 2; Question [39], Article [2], ad 3).
Reply to Objection 1: Nothing hinders a sin that is more grave in its genus from
being less grave in respect of some circumstances. Hence Augustine
hesitated to decide between a bad Catholic, and a heretic not sinning
otherwise, because although the heretic's sin is more grave generically,
it can be lessened by a circumstance, and conversely the sin of the
Catholic can, by some circumstance, be aggravated.
Reply to Objection 2: Unbelief includes both ignorance, as an accessory thereto,
and resistance to matters of faith, and in the latter respect it is a
most grave sin. In respect, however, of this ignorance, it has a certain
reason for excuse, especially when a man sins not from malice, as was the
case with the Apostle.
Reply to Objection 3: An unbeliever is more severely punished for his sin of
unbelief than another sinner is for any sin whatever, if we consider the
kind of sin. But in the case of another sin, e.g. adultery, committed by
a believer, and by an unbeliever, the believer, other things being equal,
sins more gravely than the unbeliever, both on account of his knowledge
of the truth through faith, and on account of the sacraments of faith
with which he has been satiated, and which he insults by committing sin.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 4 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that each act of an unbeliever is a sin. Because a
gloss on Rm. 14:23, "All that is not of faith is sin," says: "The whole
life of unbelievers is a sin." Now the life of unbelievers consists of
their actions. Therefore every action of an unbeliever is a sin.
Objection 2: Further, faith directs the intention. Now there can be no good
save what comes from a right intention. Therefore, among unbelievers, no
action can be good.
Objection 3: Further, when that which precedes is corrupted, that which
follows is corrupted also. Now an act of faith precedes the acts of all
the virtues. Therefore, since there is no act of faith in unbelievers,
they can do no good work, but sin in every action of theirs.
On the contrary, It is said of Cornelius, while yet an unbeliever (Acts 10:4,31), that his alms were acceptable to God. Therefore not every
action of an unbeliever is a sin, but some of his actions are good.
I answer that, As stated above (FS, Question [85], Articles [2],4) mortal sin takes
away sanctifying grace, but does not wholly corrupt the good of nature.
Since therefore, unbelief is a mortal sin, unbelievers are without grace
indeed, yet some good of nature remains in them. Consequently it is
evident that unbelievers cannot do those good works which proceed from
grace, viz. meritorious works; yet they can, to a certain extent, do
those good works for which the good of nature suffices.
Hence it does not follow that they sin in everything they do; but
whenever they do anything out of their unbelief, then they sin. For even
as one who has the faith, can commit an actual sin, venial or even
mortal, which he does not refer to the end of faith, so too, an
unbeliever can do a good deed in a matter which he does not refer to the
end of his unbelief.
Reply to Objection 1: The words quoted must be taken to mean either that the life
of unbelievers cannot be sinless, since without faith no sin is taken
away, or that whatever they do out of unbelief, is a sin. Hence the same
authority adds: "Because every one that lives or acts according to his
unbelief, sins grievously."
Reply to Objection 2: Faith directs the intention with regard to the supernatural
last end: but even the light of natural reason can direct the intention
in respect of a connatural good.
Reply to Objection 3: Unbelief does not so wholly destroy natural reason in
unbelievers, but that some knowledge of the truth remains in them,
whereby they are able to do deeds that are generically good. With regard,
however, to Cornelius, it is to be observed that he was not an
unbeliever, else his works would not have been acceptable to God, whom
none can please without faith. Now he had implicit faith, as the truth of
the Gospel was not yet made manifest: hence Peter was sent to him to give
him fuller instruction in the faith.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 5 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that there are not several species of unbelief.
For, since faith and unbelief are contrary to one another, they must be
about the same thing. Now the formal object of faith is the First Truth,
whence it derives its unity, although its matter contains many points of
belief. Therefore the object of unbelief also is the First Truth; while
the things which an unbeliever disbelieves are the matter of his
unbelief. Now the specific difference depends not on material but on
formal principles. Therefore there are not several species of unbelief,
according to the various points which the unbeliever disbelieves.
Objection 2: Further, it is possible to stray from the truth of faith in an
infinite number of ways. If therefore the various species of unbelief
correspond to the number of various errors, it would seem to follow that
there is an infinite number of species of unbelief, and consequently,
that we ought not to make these species the object of our consideration.
Objection 3: Further, the same thing does not belong to different species. Now
a man may be an unbeliever through erring about different points of
truth. Therefore diversity of errors does not make a diversity of species
of unbelief: and so there are not several species of unbelief.
On the contrary, Several species of vice are opposed to each virtue,
because "good happens in one way, but evil in many ways," according to
Dionysius (Div. Nom. iv) and the Philosopher (Ethic. ii, 6). Now faith is
a virtue. Therefore several species of vice are opposed to it.
I answer that, As stated above (FS, Question [55], Article [4]; FS, Question [64], Article [1]), every
virtue consists in following some rule of human knowledge or operation.
Now conformity to a rule happens one way in one matter, whereas a breach
of the rule happens in many ways, so that many vices are opposed to one
virtue. The diversity of the vices that are opposed to each virtue may be
considered in two ways, first, with regard to their different relations
to the virtue: and in this way there are determinate species of vices
contrary to a virtue: thus to a moral virtue one vice is opposed by
exceeding the virtue, and another, by falling short of the virtue.
Secondly, the diversity of vices opposed to one virtue may be considered
in respect of the corruption of the various conditions required for that
virtue. In this way an infinite number of vices are opposed to one
virtue, e.g. temperance or fortitude, according to the infinite number of
ways in which the various circumstances of a virtue may be corrupted, so
that the rectitude of virtue is forsaken. For this reason the
Pythagoreans held evil to be infinite.
Accordingly we must say that if unbelief be considered in comparison to
faith, there are several species of unbelief, determinate in number. For,
since the sin of unbelief consists in resisting the faith, this may
happen in two ways: either the faith is resisted before it has been
accepted, and such is the unbelief of pagans or heathens; or the
Christian faith is resisted after it has been accepted, and this either
in the figure, and such is the unbelief of the Jews, or in the very
manifestation of truth, and such is the unbelief of heretics. Hence we
may, in a general way, reckon these three as species of unbelief.
If, however, the species of unbelief be distinguished according to the
various errors that occur in matters of faith, there are not determinate
species of unbelief: for errors can be multiplied indefinitely, as
Augustine observes (De Haeresibus).
Reply to Objection 1: The formal aspect of a sin can be considered in two ways.
First, according to the intention of the sinner, in which case the thing
to which the sinner turns is the formal object of his sin, and determines
the various species of that sin. Secondly, it may be considered as an
evil, and in this case the good which is forsaken is the formal object of
the sin; which however does not derive its species from this point of
view, in fact it is a privation. We must therefore reply that the object
of unbelief is the First Truth considered as that which unbelief
forsakes, but its formal aspect, considered as that to which unbelief
turns, is the false opinion that it follows: and it is from this point of
view that unbelief derives its various species. Hence, even as charity
is one, because it adheres to the Sovereign Good, while there are various
species of vice opposed to charity, which turn away from the Sovereign
Good by turning to various temporal goods, and also in respect of various
inordinate relations to God, so too, faith is one virtue through adhering
to the one First Truth, yet there are many species of unbelief, because
unbelievers follow many false opinions.
Reply to Objection 2: This argument considers the various species of unbelief
according to various points in which errors occur.
Reply to Objection 3: Since faith is one because it believes in many things in
relation to one, so may unbelief, although it errs in many things, be one
in so far as all those things are related to one. Yet nothing hinders one
man from erring in various species of unbelief, even as one man may be
subject to various vices, and to various bodily diseases.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 6 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that the unbelief of heathens or pagans is graver
than other kinds. For just as bodily disease is graver according as it
endangers the health of a more important member of the body, so does sin
appear to be graver, according as it is opposed to that which holds a
more important place in virtue. Now that which is most important in
faith, is belief in the unity of God, from which the heathens deviate by
believing in many gods. Therefore their unbelief is the gravest of all.
Objection 2: Further, among heresies, the more detestable are those which
contradict the truth of faith in more numerous and more important points:
thus, the heresy of Arius, who severed the Godhead, was more detestable
than that of Nestorius who severed the humanity of Christ from the Person
of God the Son. Now the heathens deny the faith in more numerous and more
important points than Jews and heretics; since they do not accept the
faith at all. Therefore their unbelief is the gravest.
Objection 3: Further, every good diminishes evil. Now there is some good in
the Jews, since they believe in the Old Testament as being from God, and
there is some good in heretics, since they venerate the New Testament.
Therefore they sin less grievously than heathens, who receive neither
Testament.
On the contrary, It is written (2 Pt. 2:21): "It had been better for
them not to have known the way of justice, than after they have known it,
to turn back." Now the heathens have not known the way of justice,
whereas heretics and Jews have abandoned it after knowing it in some way.
Therefore theirs is the graver sin.
I answer that, As stated above (Article [5]), two things may be considered in
unbelief. One of these is its relation to faith: and from this point of
view, he who resists the faith after accepting it, sins more grievously
against faith, than he who resists it without having accepted it, even as
he who fails to fulfil what he has promised, sins more grievously than if
he had never promised it. In this way the unbelief of heretics, who
confess their belief in the Gospel, and resist that faith by corrupting
it, is a more grievous sin than that of the Jews, who have never accepted
the Gospel faith. Since, however, they accepted the figure of that faith
in the Old Law, which they corrupt by their false interpretations, their
unbelief is a more grievous sin than that of the heathens, because the
latter have not accepted the Gospel faith in any way at all.
The second thing to be considered in unbelief is the corruption of
matters of faith. In this respect, since heathens err on more points than
Jews, and these in more points than heretics, the unbelief of heathens is
more grievous than the unbelief of the Jews, and that of the Jews than
that of the heretics, except in such cases as that of the Manichees, who,
in matters of faith, err even more than heathens do.
Of these two gravities the first surpasses the second from the point of
view of guilt; since, as stated above (Article [1]) unbelief has the character
of guilt, from its resisting faith rather than from the mere absence of
faith, for the latter as was stated (Article [1]) seems rather to bear the
character of punishment. Hence, speaking absolutely, the unbelief of
heretics is the worst.
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 7 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that one ought not to dispute with unbelievers in
public. For the Apostle says (2 Tim. 2:14): "Contend not in words, for it
is to no profit, but to the subverting of the hearers." But it is
impossible to dispute with unbelievers publicly without contending in
words. Therefore one ought not to dispute publicly with unbelievers.
Objection 2: Further, the law of Martianus Augustus confirmed by the canons
[*De Sum. Trin. Cod. lib. i, leg. Nemo] expresses itself thus: "It is an
insult to the judgment of the most religious synod, if anyone ventures to
debate or dispute in public about matters which have once been judged and
disposed of." Now all matters of faith have been decided by the holy
councils. Therefore it is an insult to the councils, and consequently a
grave sin to presume to dispute in public about matters of faith.
Objection 3: Further, disputations are conducted by means of arguments. But an argument is a reason in settlement of a dubious matter: whereas things that are of faith, being most certain, ought not to be a matter of doubt. Therefore one ought not to dispute in public about matters of faith.
On the contrary, It is written (Acts 9:22,29) that "Saul increased much
more in strength, and confounded the Jews," and that "he spoke . . . to
the gentiles and disputed with the Greeks."
I answer that, In disputing about the faith, two things must be
observed: one on the part of the disputant; the other on the part of his
hearers. On the part of the disputant, we must consider his intention.
For if he were to dispute as though he had doubts about the faith, and
did not hold the truth of faith for certain, and as though he intended to
probe it with arguments, without doubt he would sin, as being doubtful of
the faith and an unbeliever. On the other hand, it is praiseworthy to
dispute about the faith in order to confute errors, or for practice.
On the part of the hearers we must consider whether those who hear the
disputation are instructed and firm in the faith, or simple and wavering.
As to those who are well instructed and firm in the faith, there can be
no danger in disputing about the faith in their presence. But as to
simple-minded people, we must make a distinction; because either they are
provoked and molested by unbelievers, for instance, Jews or heretics, or
pagans who strive to corrupt the faith in them, or else they are not
subject to provocation in this matter, as in those countries where there
are not unbelievers. In the first case it is necessary to dispute in
public about the faith, provided there be those who are equal and adapted
to the task of confuting errors; since in this way simple people are
strengthened in the faith, and unbelievers are deprived of the
opportunity to deceive, while if those who ought to withstand the
perverters of the truth of faith were silent, this would tend to
strengthen error. Hence Gregory says (Pastor. ii, 4): "Even as a
thoughtless speech gives rise to error, so does an indiscreet silence
leave those in error who might have been instructed." On the other hand,
in the second case it is dangerous to dispute in public about the faith,
in the presence of simple people, whose faith for this very reason is
more firm, that they have never heard anything differing from what they
believe. Hence it is not expedient for them to hear what unbelievers have
to say against the faith.
Reply to Objection 1: The Apostle does not entirely forbid disputations, but such
as are inordinate, and consist of contentious words rather than of sound
speeches.
Reply to Objection 2: That law forbade those public disputations about the faith,
which arise from doubting the faith, but not those which are for the
safeguarding thereof.
Reply to Objection 3: One ought to dispute about matters of faith, not as though
one doubted about them, but in order to make the truth known, and to
confute errors. For, in order to confirm the faith, it is necessary
sometimes to dispute with unbelievers, sometimes by defending the faith,
according to 1 Pt. 3:15: "Being ready always to satisfy everyone that
asketh you a reason of that hope and faith which is in you [*Vulg.: 'Of
that hope which is in you' St. Thomas' reading is apparently taken from
Bede]." Sometimes again, it is necessary, in order to convince those who
are in error, according to Titus 1:9: "That he may be able to exhort in
sound doctrine and to convince the gainsayers."
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 8 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that unbelievers ought by no means to be compelled
to the faith. For it is written (Mt. 13:28) that the servants of the
householder, in whose field cockle had been sown, asked him: "Wilt thou
that we go and gather it up?" and that he answered: "No, lest perhaps
gathering up the cockle, you root up the wheat also together with it": on
which passage Chrysostom says (Hom. xlvi in Matth.): "Our Lord says this
so as to forbid the slaying of men. For it is not right to slay heretics,
because if you do you will necessarily slay many innocent persons."
Therefore it seems that for the same reason unbelievers ought not to be
compelled to the faith.
Objection 2: Further, we read in the Decretals (Dist. xlv can., De Judaeis):
"The holy synod prescribes, with regard to the Jews, that for the future,
none are to be compelled to believe." Therefore, in like manner, neither
should unbelievers be compelled to the faith.
Objection 3: Further, Augustine says (Tract. xxvi in Joan.) that "it is
possible for a man to do other things against his will, but he cannot
believe unless he is willing." Therefore it seems that unbelievers ought
not to be compelled to the faith.
Objection 4: It is said in God's person (Ezech. 18:32 [*Ezech. 33:11]): "I
desire not the death of the sinner [Vulg.: 'of him that dieth']." Now we
ought to conform our will to the Divine will, as stated above (FS, Question [19], Articles [9],10). Therefore we should not even wish unbelievers to be put to
death.
On the contrary, It is written (Lk. 14:23): "Go out into the highways
and hedges; and compel them to come in." Now men enter into the house of
God, i.e. into Holy Church, by faith. Therefore some ought to be
compelled to the faith.
I answer that, Among unbelievers there are some who have never received
the faith, such as the heathens and the Jews: and these are by no means
to be compelled to the faith, in order that they may believe, because to
believe depends on the will: nevertheless they should be compelled by the
faithful, if it be possible to do so, so that they do not hinder the
faith, by their blasphemies, or by their evil persuasions, or even by
their open persecutions. It is for this reason that Christ's faithful
often wage war with unbelievers, not indeed for the purpose of forcing
them to believe, because even if they were to conquer them, and take them
prisoners, they should still leave them free to believe, if they will,
but in order to prevent them from hindering the faith of Christ.
On the other hand, there are unbelievers who at some time have accepted
the faith, and professed it, such as heretics and all apostates: such
should be submitted even to bodily compulsion, that they may fulfil what
they have promised, and hold what they, at one time, received.
Reply to Objection 1: Some have understood the authority quoted to forbid, not
the excommunication but the slaying of heretics, as appears from the
words of Chrysostom. Augustine too, says (Ep. ad Vincent. xciii) of
himself: "It was once my opinion that none should be compelled to union
with Christ, that we should deal in words, and fight with arguments.
However this opinion of mine is undone, not by words of contradiction,
but by convincing examples. Because fear of the law was so profitable,
that many say: Thanks be to the Lord Who has broken our chains asunder."
Accordingly the meaning of Our Lord's words, "Suffer both to grow until
the harvest," must be gathered from those which precede, "lest perhaps
gathering up the cockle, you root the wheat also together with it." For,
Augustine says (Contra Ep. Parmen. iii, 2) "these words show that when
this is not to be feared, that is to say, when a man's crime is so
publicly known, and so hateful to all, that he has no defenders, or none
such as might cause a schism, the severity of discipline should not
slacken."
Reply to Objection 2: Those Jews who have in no way received the faith, ought not
by no means to be compelled to the faith: if, however, they have received
it, they ought to be compelled to keep it, as is stated in the same
chapter.
Reply to Objection 3: Just as taking a vow is a matter of will, and keeping a
vow, a matter of obligation, so acceptance of the faith is a matter of
the will, whereas keeping the faith, when once one has received it, is a
matter of obligation. Wherefore heretics should be compelled to keep the
faith. Thus Augustine says to the Count Boniface (Ep. clxxxv): "What do
these people mean by crying out continually: 'We may believe or not
believe just as we choose. Whom did Christ compel?' They should remember
that Christ at first compelled Paul and afterwards taught Him."
Reply to Objection 4: As Augustine says in the same letter, "none of us wishes
any heretic to perish. But the house of David did not deserve to have
peace, unless his son Absalom had been killed in the war which he had
raised against his father. Thus if the Catholic Church gathers together
some of the perdition of others, she heals the sorrow of her maternal
heart by the delivery of so many nations."
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 9 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that it is lawful to communicate with unbelievers.
For the Apostle says (1 Cor. 10:27): "If any of them that believe not,
invite you, and you be willing to go, eat of anything that is set before
you." And Chrysostom says (Hom. xxv super Epist. ad Heb.): "If you wish
to go to dine with pagans, we permit it without any reservation." Now to
sit at table with anyone is to communicate with him. Therefore it is
lawful to communicate with unbelievers.
Objection 2: Further, the Apostle says (1 Cor. 5:12): "What have I to do to
judge them that are without?" Now unbelievers are without. When,
therefore, the Church forbids the faithful to communicate with certain
people, it seems that they ought not to be forbidden to communicate with
unbelievers.
Objection 3: Further, a master cannot employ his servant, unless he
communicate with him, at least by word, since the master moves his
servant by command. Now Christians can have unbelievers, either Jews, or
pagans, or Saracens, for servants. Therefore they can lawfully
communicate with them.
On the contrary, It is written (Dt. 7:2,3): "Thou shalt make no league
with them, nor show mercy to them; neither shalt thou make marriages with
them": and a gloss on Lev. 15:19, "The woman who at the return of the
month," etc. says: "It is so necessary to shun idolatry, that we should
not come in touch with idolaters or their disciples, nor have any
dealings with them."
I answer that, Communication with a particular person is forbidden to
the faithful, in two ways: first, as a punishment of the person with whom
they are forbidden to communicate; secondly, for the safety of those who
are forbidden to communicate with others. Both motives can be gathered
from the Apostle's words (1 Cor. 5:6). For after he had pronounced
sentence of excommunication, he adds as his reason: "Know you not that a
little leaven corrupts the whole lump?" and afterwards he adds the reason
on the part of the punishment inflicted by the sentence of the Church
when he says (1 Cor. 5:12): "Do not you judge them that are within?"
Accordingly, in the first way the Church does not forbid the faithful to
communicate with unbelievers, who have not in any way received the
Christian faith, viz. with pagans and Jews, because she has not the right
to exercise spiritual judgment over them, but only temporal judgment, in
the case when, while dwelling among Christians they are guilty of some
misdemeanor, and are condemned by the faithful to some temporal
punishment. On the other hand, in this way, i.e. as a punishment, the
Church forbids the faithful to communicate with those unbelievers who
have forsaken the faith they once received, either by corrupting the
faith, as heretics, or by entirely renouncing the faith, as apostates,
because the Church pronounces sentence of excommunication on both.
With regard to the second way, it seems that one ought to distinguish
according to the various conditions of persons, circumstances and time.
For some are firm in the faith; and so it is to be hoped that their
communicating with unbelievers will lead to the conversion of the latter
rather than to the aversion of the faithful from the faith. These are not
to be forbidden to communicate with unbelievers who have not received
the faith, such as pagans or Jews, especially if there be some urgent
necessity for so doing. But in the case of simple people and those who
are weak in the faith, whose perversion is to be feared as a probable
result, they should be forbidden to communicate with unbelievers, and
especially to be on very familiar terms with them, or to communicate with
them without necessity.
This suffices for the Reply to the First Objection.
Reply to Objection 2: The Church does not exercise judgment against unbelievers
in the point of inflicting spiritual punishment on them: but she does
exercise judgment over some of them in the matter of temporal punishment.
It is under this head that sometimes the Church, for certain special
sins, withdraws the faithful from communication with certain unbelievers.
Reply to Objection 3: There is more probability that a servant who is ruled by
his master's commands, will be converted to the faith of his master who
is a believer, than if the case were the reverse: and so the faithful are
not forbidden to have unbelieving servants. If, however, the master were
in danger, through communicating with such a servant, he should send him
away, according to Our Lord's command (Mt. 18:8): "If . . . thy foot
scandalize thee, cut it off, and cast it from thee."
With regard to the argument in the contrary [*The Leonine Edition gives
this solution before the Reply OBJ 2] sense the reply is that the Lord
gave this command in reference to those nations into whose territory the
Jews were about to enter. For the latter were inclined to idolatry, so
that it was to be feared lest, through frequent dealings with those
nations, they should be estranged from the faith: hence the text goes on
(Dt. 7:4): "For she will turn away thy son from following Me."
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 10 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that unbelievers may have authority or dominion
over the faithful. For the Apostle says (1 Tim. 6:1): "Whosoever are
servants under the yoke, let them count their masters worthy of all
honor": and it is clear that he is speaking of unbelievers, since he adds
(1 Tim. 6:2): "But they that have believing masters, let them not despise
them." Moreover it is written (1 Pt. 2:18): "Servants be subject to your
masters with all fear, not only to the good and gentle, but also to the
froward." Now this command would not be contained in the apostolic
teaching unless unbelievers could have authority over the faithful.
Therefore it seems that unbelievers can have authority over the faithful.
Objection 2: Further, all the members of a prince's household are his
subjects. Now some of the faithful were members of unbelieving princes'
households, for we read in the Epistle to the Philippians (4:22): "All
the saints salute you, especially they that are of Caesar's household,"
referring to Nero, who was an unbeliever. Therefore unbelievers can have
authority over the faithful.
Objection 3: Further, according to the Philosopher (Polit. i, 2) a slave is
his master's instrument in matters concerning everyday life, even as a
craftsman's laborer is his instrument in matters concerning the working
of his art. Now, in such matters, a believer can be subject to an
unbeliever, for he may work on an unbeliever's farm. Therefore
unbelievers may have authority over the faithful even as to dominion.
On the contrary, Those who are in authority can pronounce judgment on
those over whom they are placed. But unbelievers cannot pronounce
judgment on the faithful, for the Apostle says (1 Cor. 6:1): "Dare any of
you, having a matter against another, go to be judged before the unjust,"
i.e. unbelievers, "and not before the saints?" Therefore it seems that
unbelievers cannot have authority over the faithful.
I answer that, That this question may be considered in two ways. First,
we may speak of dominion or authority of unbelievers over the faithful as
of a thing to be established for the first time. This ought by no means
to be allowed, since it would provoke scandal and endanger the faith, for
subjects are easily influenced by their superiors to comply with their
commands, unless the subjects are of great virtue: moreover unbelievers
hold the faith in contempt, if they see the faithful fall away. Hence the
Apostle forbade the faithful to go to law before an unbelieving judge.
And so the Church altogether forbids unbelievers to acquire dominion over
believers, or to have authority over them in any capacity whatever.
Secondly, we may speak of dominion or authority, as already in force:
and here we must observe that dominion and authority are institutions of
human law, while the distinction between faithful and unbelievers arises
from the Divine law. Now the Divine law which is the law of grace, does
not do away with human law which is the law of natural reason. Wherefore
the distinction between faithful and unbelievers, considered in itself,
does not do away with dominion and authority of unbelievers over the
faithful.
Nevertheless this right of dominion or authority can be justly done away
with by the sentence or ordination of the Church who has the authority of
God: since unbelievers in virtue of their unbelief deserve to forfeit
their power over the faithful who are converted into children of God.
This the Church does sometimes, and sometimes not. For among those
unbelievers who are subject, even in temporal matters, to the Church and
her members, the Church made the law that if the slave of a Jew became a
Christian, he should forthwith receive his freedom, without paying any
price, if he should be a "vernaculus," i.e. born in slavery; and
likewise if, when yet an unbeliever, he had been bought for his service:
if, however, he had been bought for sale, then he should be offered for
sale within three months. Nor does the Church harm them in this, because
since those Jews themselves are subject to the Church, she can dispose of
their possessions, even as secular princes have enacted many laws to be
observed by their subjects, in favor of liberty. On the other hand, the
Church has not applied the above law to those unbelievers who are not
subject to her or her members, in temporal matters, although she has the
right to do so: and this, in order to avoid scandal, for as Our Lord
showed (Mt. 17:25,26) that He could be excused from paying the tribute,
because "the children are free," yet He ordered the tribute to be paid in
order to avoid giving scandal. Thus Paul too, after saying that servants
should honor their masters, adds, "lest the name of the Lord and His
doctrine be blasphemed."
This suffices for the Reply to the First Objection.
Reply to Objection 2: The authority of Caesar preceded the distinction of
faithful from unbelievers. Hence it was not cancelled by the conversion
of some to the faith. Moreover it was a good thing that there should be a
few of the faithful in the emperor's household, that they might defend
the rest of the faithful. Thus the Blessed Sebastian encouraged those
whom he saw faltering under torture, and, the while, remained hidden
under the military cloak in the palace of Diocletian.
Reply to Objection 3: Slaves are subject to their masters for their whole
lifetime, and are subject to their overseers in everything: whereas the
craftsman's laborer is subject to him for certain special works. Hence it
would be more dangerous for unbelievers to have dominion or authority
over the faithful, than that they should be allowed to employ them in
some craft. Wherefore the Church permits Christians to work on the land
of Jews, because this does not entail their living together with them.
Thus Solomon besought the King of Tyre to send master workmen to hew the
trees, as related in 3 Kgs. 5:6. Yet, if there be reason to fear that the
faithful will be perverted by such communications and dealings, they
should be absolutely forbidden.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 11 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that rites of unbelievers ought not to be
tolerated. For it is evident that unbelievers sin in observing their
rites: and not to prevent a sin, when one can, seems to imply consent
therein, as a gloss observes on Rm. 1:32: "Not only they that do them,
but they also that consent to them that do them." Therefore it is a sin
to tolerate their rites.
Objection 2: Further, the rites of the Jews are compared to idolatry, because
a gloss on Gal. 5:1, "Be not held again under the yoke of bondage," says:
"The bondage of that law was not lighter than that of idolatry." But it
would not be allowable for anyone to observe the rites of idolatry, in
fact Christian princes at first caused the temples of idols to be closed,
and afterwards, to be destroyed, as Augustine relates (De Civ. Dei xviii,
54). Therefore it follows that even the rites of Jews ought not to be
tolerated.
Objection 3: Further, unbelief is the greatest of sins, as stated above (Article [3]). Now other sins such as adultery, theft and the like, are not
tolerated, but are punishable by law. Therefore neither ought the rites
of unbelievers to be tolerated.
On the contrary, Gregory [*Regist. xi, Ep. 15: cf. Decret., dist. xlv,
can., Qui sincera] says, speaking of the Jews: "They should be allowed to
observe all their feasts, just as hitherto they and their fathers have
for ages observed them."
I answer that, Human government is derived from the Divine government,
and should imitate it. Now although God is all-powerful and supremely
good, nevertheless He allows certain evils to take place in the universe,
which He might prevent, lest, without them, greater goods might be
forfeited, or greater evils ensue. Accordingly in human government also,
those who are in authority, rightly tolerate certain evils, lest certain
goods be lost, or certain greater evils be incurred: thus Augustine says
(De Ordine ii, 4): "If you do away with harlots, the world will be
convulsed with lust." Hence, though unbelievers sin in their rites, they
may be tolerated, either on account of some good that ensues therefrom,
or because of some evil avoided. Thus from the fact that the Jews observe
their rites, which, of old, foreshadowed the truth of the faith which we
hold, there follows this good---that our very enemies bear witness to our
faith, and that our faith is represented in a figure, so to speak. For
this reason they are tolerated in the observance of their rites.
On the other hand, the rites of other unbelievers, which are neither
truthful nor profitable are by no means to be tolerated, except perchance
in order to avoid an evil, e.g. the scandal or disturbance that might
ensue, or some hindrance to the salvation of those who if they were
unmolested might gradually be converted to the faith. For this reason the
Church, at times, has tolerated the rites even of heretics and pagans,
when unbelievers were very numerous.
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 10 [<< | >>]
Article: 12 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that the children of Jews and of other unbelievers
ought to be baptized against their parents' will. For the bond of
marriage is stronger than the right of parental authority over children,
since the right of parental authority can be made to cease, when a son is
set at liberty; whereas the marriage bond cannot be severed by man,
according to Mt. 19:6: "What . . . God hath joined together let no man
put asunder." And yet the marriage bond is broken on account of unbelief:
for the Apostle says (1 Cor. 7:15): "If the unbeliever depart, let him
depart. For a brother or sister is not under servitude in such cases":
and a canon [*Can. Uxor legitima, and Idololatria, qu. i] says that "if
the unbelieving partner is unwilling to abide with the other, without
insult to their Creator, then the other partner is not bound to
cohabitation." Much more, therefore, does unbelief abrogate the right of
unbelieving parents' authority over their children: and consequently
their children may be baptized against their parents' will.
Objection 2: Further, one is more bound to succor a man who is in danger of
everlasting death, than one who is in danger of temporal death. Now it
would be a sin, if one saw a man in danger of temporal death and failed
to go to his aid. Since, then, the children of Jews and other unbelievers
are in danger of everlasting death, should they be left to their parents
who would imbue them with their unbelief, it seems that they ought to be
taken away from them and baptized, and instructed in the faith.
Objection 3: Further, the children of a bondsman are themselves bondsmen, and
under the power of his master. Now the Jews are bondsmen of kings and
princes: therefore their children are also. Consequently kings and
princes have the power to do what they will with Jewish children.
Therefore no injustice is committed if they baptize them against their
parents' wishes.
Objection 4: Further, every man belongs more to God, from Whom he has his
soul, than to his carnal father, from whom he has his body. Therefore it
is not unjust if Jewish children be taken away from their parents, and
consecrated to God in Baptism.
Objection 5: Further, Baptism avails for salvation more than preaching does,
since Baptism removes forthwith the stain of sin and the debt of
punishment, and opens the gate of heaven. Now if danger ensue through not
preaching, it is imputed to him who omitted to preach, according to the
words of Ezech. 33:6 about the man who "sees the sword coming and sounds
not the trumpet." Much more therefore, if Jewish children are lost
through not being baptized are they accounted guilty of sin, who could
have baptized them and did not.
On the contrary, Injustice should be done to no man. Now it would be an
injustice to Jews if their children were to be baptized against their
will, since they would lose the rights of parental authority over their
children as soon as these were Christians. Therefore these should not be
baptized against their parents' will.
I answer that, The custom of the Church has very great authority and
ought to be jealously observed in all things, since the very doctrine of
catholic doctors derives its authority from the Church. Hence we ought to
abide by the authority of the Church rather than by that of an Augustine
or a Jerome or of any doctor whatever. Now it was never the custom of the
Church to baptize the children of the Jews against the will of their
parents, although at times past there have been many very powerful
catholic princes like Constantine and Theodosius, with whom most holy
bishops have been on most friendly terms, as Sylvester with Constantine,
and Ambrose with Theodosius, who would certainly not have failed to
obtain this favor from them if it had been at all reasonable. It seems
therefore hazardous to repeat this assertion, that the children of Jews
should be baptized against their parents' wishes, in contradiction to the
Church's custom observed hitherto.
There are two reasons for this custom. One is on account of the danger
to the faith. For children baptized before coming to the use of reason,
afterwards when they come to perfect age, might easily be persuaded by
their parents to renounce what they had unknowingly embraced; and this
would be detrimental to the faith.
The other reason is that it is against natural justice. For a child is
by nature part of its father: thus, at first, it is not distinct from its
parents as to its body, so long as it is enfolded within its mother's
womb; and later on after birth, and before it has the use of its
free-will, it is enfolded in the care of its parents, which is like a
spiritual womb, for so long as man has not the use of reason, he differs
not from an irrational animal; so that even as an ox or a horse belongs
to someone who, according to the civil law, can use them when he likes,
as his own instrument, so, according to the natural law, a son, before
coming to the use of reason, is under his father's care. Hence it would
be contrary to natural justice, if a child, before coming to the use of
reason, were to be taken away from its parents' custody, or anything done
to it against its parents' wish. As soon, however, as it begins to have
the use of its free-will, it begins to belong to itself, and is able to
look after itself, in matters concerning the Divine or the natural law,
and then it should be induced, not by compulsion but by persuasion, to
embrace the faith: it can then consent to the faith, and be baptized,
even against its parents' wish; but not before it comes to the use of
reason. Hence it is said of the children of the fathers of old that they
were saved in the faith of their parents; whereby we are given to
understand that it is the parents' duty to look after the salvation of
their children, especially before they come to the use of reason.
Reply to Objection 1: In the marriage bond, both husband and wife have the use of
the free-will, and each can assent to the faith without the other's
consent. But this does not apply to a child before it comes to the use of
reason: yet the comparison holds good after the child has come to the use
of reason, if it is willing to be converted.
Reply to Objection 2: No one should be snatched from natural death against the
order of civil law: for instance, if a man were condemned by the judge to
temporal death, nobody ought to rescue him by violence: hence no one
ought to break the order of the natural law, whereby a child is in the
custody of its father, in order to rescue it from the danger of
everlasting death.
Reply to Objection 3: Jews are bondsmen of princes by civil bondage, which does
not exclude the order of natural or Divine law.
Reply to Objection 4: Man is directed to God by his reason, whereby he can know
Him. Hence a child before coming to the use of reason, in the natural
order of things, is directed to God by its parents' reason, under whose
care it lies by nature: and it is for them to dispose of the child in all
matters relating to God.
Reply to Objection 5: The peril that ensues from the omission of preaching,
threatens only those who are entrusted with the duty of preaching. Hence
it had already been said (Ezech. 3:17): "I have made thee a watchman to
the children [Vulg.: 'house'] of Israel." On the other hand, to provide
the sacraments of salvation for the children of unbelievers is the duty
of their parents. Hence it is they whom the danger threatens, if through
being deprived of the sacraments their children fail to obtain salvation.