Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 106 [<< | >>]
We must now consider thankfulness or gratitude, and ingratitude.
Concerning thankfulness there are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether thankfulness is a special virtue distinct from other virtues?
(2) Who owes more thanks to God, the innocent or the penitent?
(3) Whether man is always bound to give thanks for human favors?
(4) Whether thanksgiving should be deferred?
(5) Whether thanksgiving should be measured according to the favor
received or the disposition of the giver?
(6) Whether one ought to pay back more than one has received?
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 106 [<< | >>]
Article: 1 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It seems that thankfulness is not a special virtue, distinct from
other virtue. For we have received the greatest benefits from God, and
from our parents. Now the honor which we pay to God in return belongs to
the virtue of religion, and the honor with which we repay our parents
belongs to the virtue of piety. Therefore thankfulness or gratitude is
not distinct from the other virtues.
Objection 2: Further, proportionate repayment belongs to commutative justice,
according to the Philosopher (Ethic. v, 4). Now the purpose of giving
thanks is repayment (Ethic. 5,4). Therefore thanksgiving, which belongs
to gratitude, is an act of justice. Therefore gratitude is not a special
virtue, distinct from other virtues.
Objection 3: Further, acknowledgment of favor received is requisite for the
preservation of friendship, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. viii,
13; ix, 1). Now friendship is associated with all the virtues, since they
are the reason for which man is loved. Therefore thankfulness or
gratitude, to which it belongs to repay favors received, is not a special
virtue.
On the contrary, Tully reckons thankfulness a special part of justice
(De Invent. Rhet. ii).
I answer that, As stated above (FS, Question [60], Article [3]), the nature of the debt
to be paid must needs vary according to various causes giving rise to the
debt, yet so that the greater always includes the lesser. Now the cause
of debt is found primarily and chiefly in God, in that He is the first
principle of all our goods: secondarily it is found in our father,
because he is the proximate principle of our begetting and upbringing:
thirdly it is found in the person that excels in dignity, from whom
general favors proceed; fourthly it is found in a benefactor, from whom
we have received particular and private favors, on account of which we
are under particular obligation to him.
Accordingly, since what we owe God, or our father, or a person excelling
in dignity, is not the same as what we owe a benefactor from whom we have
received some particular favor, it follows that after religion, whereby
we pay God due worship, and piety, whereby we worship our parents, and
observance, whereby we worship persons excelling in dignity, there is
thankfulness or gratitude, whereby we give thanks to our benefactors. And
it is distinct from the foregoing virtues, just as each of these is
distinct from the one that precedes, as falling short thereof.
Reply to Objection 1: Just as religion is superexcelling piety, so is it
excelling thankfulness or gratitude: wherefore giving thanks to God was
reckoned above (Question [83], Article [17]) among things pertaining to religion.
Reply to Objection 2: Proportionate repayment belongs to commutative justice,
when it answers to the legal due; for instance when it is contracted that
so much be paid for so much. But the repayment that belongs to the virtue
of thankfulness or gratitude answers to the moral debt, and is paid
spontaneously. Hence thanksgiving is less thankful when compelled, as
Seneca observes (De Beneficiis iii).
Reply to Objection 3: Since true friendship is based on virtue, whatever there is
contrary to virtue in a friend is an obstacle to friendship, and whatever
in him is virtuous is an incentive to friendship. In this way friendship
is preserved by repayment of favors, although repayment of favors belongs
specially to the virtue of gratitude.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 106 [<< | >>]
Article: 2 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It seems that the innocent is more bound to give thanks to God
than the penitent. For the greater the gift one has received from God,
the more one is bound to give Him thanks. Now the gift of innocence is
greater than that of justice restored. Therefore it seems that the
innocent is more bound to give thanks to God than the penitent.
Objection 2: Further, a man owes love to his benefactor just as he owes him
gratitude. Now Augustine says (Confess. ii): "What man, weighing his own
infirmity, would dare to ascribe his purity and innocence to his own
strength; that so he should love Thee the less, as if he had less needed
Thy mercy, whereby Thou remittest sins to those that turn to Thee?" And
farther on he says: "And for this let him love Thee as much, yea and
more, since by Whom he sees me to have been recovered from such deep
torpor of sin, by Him he sees himself to have been from the like torpor
of sin preserved." Therefore the innocent is also more bound to give
thanks than the penitent.
Objection 3: Further, the more a gratuitous favor is continuous, the greater
the thanksgiving due for it. Now the favor of divine grace is more
continuous in the innocent than in the penitent. For Augustine says
(Confess. iii): "To Thy grace I ascribe it, and to Thy mercy, that Thou
hast melted away my sins as it were ice. To Thy grace I ascribe also
whatsoever I have not done of evil; for what might I not have done? . . .
Yea, all I confess to have been forgiven me, both what evils I committed
by my own wilfulness, and what by Thy guidance committed not." Therefore
the innocent is more bound to give thanks than the penitent.
On the contrary, It is written (Lk. 7:43): "To whom more is forgiven, he
loveth more [*Vulg.: 'To whom less is forgiven, he loveth less' Lk.
7:47]." Therefore for the same reason he is bound to greater thanksgiving.
I answer that, Thanksgiving [gratiarum actio] in the recipient
corresponds to the favor [gratia] of the giver: so that when there is
greater favor on the part of the giver, greater thanks are due on the
part of the recipient. Now a favor is something bestowed "gratis":
wherefore on the part of the giver the favor may be greater on two
counts. First, owing to the quantity of the thing given: and in this way
the innocent owes greater thanksgiving, because he receives a greater
gift from God, also, absolutely speaking, a more continuous gift, other
things being equal. Secondly, a favor may be said to be greater, because
it is given more gratuitously; and in this sense the penitent is more
bound to give thanks than the innocent, because what he receives from God
is more gratuitously given: since, whereas he was deserving of
punishment, he has received grace. Wherefore, although the gift bestowed
on the innocent is, considered absolutely, greater, yet the gift bestowed
on the penitent is greater in relation to him: even as a small gift
bestowed on a poor man is greater to him than a great gift is to a rich
man. And since actions are about singulars, in matters of action, we have
to take note of what is such here and now, rather than of what is such
absolutely, as the Philosopher observes (Ethic. iii) in treating of the
voluntary and the involuntary.
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 106 [<< | >>]
Article: 3 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It seems that the a man is not bound to give thanks to every
benefactor. For a man may benefit himself just as he may harm himself,
according to Ecclus. 14:5, "He that is evil to himself, to whom will he
be good?" But a man cannot thank himself, since thanksgiving seems to
pass from one person to another. Therefore thanksgiving is not due to
every benefactor.
Objection 2: Further, gratitude is a repayment of an act of grace. But some
favors are granted without grace, and are rudely, slowly and grudgingly
given. Therefore gratitude is not always due to a benefactor.
Objection 3: Further, no thanks are due to one who works for his own profit.
But sometimes people bestow favors for their own profit. Therefore thanks
are not due to them.
Objection 4: Further, no thanks are due to a slave, for all that he is belongs
to his master. Yet sometimes a slave does a good turn to his master.
Therefore gratitude is not due to every benefactor .
Objection 5: Further, no one is bound to do what he cannot do equitably and
advantageously. Now it happens at times that the benefactor is very well
off, and it would be of no advantage to him to be repaid for a favor he
has bestowed. Again it happens sometimes that the benefactor from being
virtuous has become wicked, so that it would not seem equitable to repay
him. Also the recipient of a favor may be a poor man, and is quite unable
to repay. Therefore seemingly a man is not always bound to repayment for
favors received.
Objection 6: Further, no one is bound to do for another what is inexpedient
and hurtful to him. Now sometimes it happens that repayment of a favor
would be hurtful or useless to the person repaid. Therefore favors are
not always to be repaid by gratitude.
On the contrary, It is written (1 Thess. 5:18): "In all things give
thanks."
I answer that, Every effect turns naturally to its cause; wherefore
Dionysius says (Div. Nom. i) that "God turns all things to Himself
because He is the cause of all": for the effect must needs always be
directed to the end of the agent. Now it is evident that a benefactor, as
such, is cause of the beneficiary. Hence the natural order requires that
he who has received a favor should, by repaying the favor, turn to his
benefactor according to the mode of each. And, as stated above with
regard to a father (Question [31], Article [3]; Question [101], Article [2]), a man owes his
benefactor, as such, honor and reverence, since the latter stands to him
in the relation of principle; but accidentally he owes him assistance or
support, if he need it.
Reply to Objection 1: In the words of Seneca (1 Benef. v), "just as a man is
liberal who gives not to himself but to others, and gracious who forgives
not himself but others, and merciful who is moved, not by his own
misfortunes but by another's, so too, no man confers a favor on himself,
he is but following the bent of his nature, which moves him to resist
what hurts him, and to seek what is profitable." Wherefore in things that
one does for oneself, there is no place for gratitude or ingratitude,
since a man cannot deny himself a thing except by keeping it.
Nevertheless things which are properly spoken of in relation to others
are spoken of metaphorically in relation to oneself, as the Philosopher
states regarding justice (Ethic. v, 11), in so far, to wit, as the
various parts of man are considered as though they were various persons.
Reply to Objection 2: It is the mark of a happy disposition to see good rather
than evil. Wherefore if someone has conferred a favor, not as he ought to
have conferred it, the recipient should not for that reason withhold his
thanks. Yet he owes less thanks, than if the favor had been conferred
duly, since in fact the favor is less, for, as Seneca remarks (De Benef.
ii.) "promptness enhances, delay discounts a favor."
Reply to Objection 3: As Seneca observes (De Benef. vi), "it matters much whether
a person does a kindness to us for his own sake, or for ours, or for both
his and ours. He that considers himself only, and benefits because cannot
otherwise benefit himself, seems to me like a man who seeks fodder for
his cattle." And farther on: "If he has done it for me in common with
himself, having both of us in his mind, I am ungrateful and not merely
unjust, unless I rejoice that what was profitable to him is profitable to
me also. It is the height of malevolence to refuse to recognize a
kindness, unless the giver has been the loser thereby."
Reply to Objection 4: As Seneca observes (De Benef. iii), "when a slave does what
is wont to be demanded of a slave, it is part of his service: when he
does more than a slave is bound to do, it is a favor: for as soon as he
does anything from a motive of friendship, if indeed that be his motive,
it is no longer called service." Wherefore gratitude is due even to a
slave, when he does more than his duty.
Reply to Objection 5: A poor man is certainly not ungrateful if he does what he
can. For since kindness depends on the heart rather than on the deed, so
too gratitude depends chiefly the heart. Hence Seneca says (De Benef.
ii): "Who receives a favor gratefully, has already begun to pay it back:
and that we are grateful for favors received should be shown by the
outpourings of the heart, not only in his hearing but everywhere." From
this it is evident that however well off a man may be, it is possible to
thank him for his kindness by showing him reverence and honor. Wherefore
the Philosopher says (Ethic. viii, 14): "He that abounds should be
repaid with honor, he that is in want should be repaid with money": and
Seneca writes (De Benef. vi): "There are many ways of repaying those who
are well off, whatever we happen to owe them; such as good advice,
frequent fellowship, affable and pleasant conversation without flattery."
Therefore there is no need for a man to desire neediness or distress in
his benefactor before repaying his kindness, because, as Seneca says (De
Benef. vi), "it were inhuman to desire this in one from whom you have
received no favor; how much more so to desire it in one whose kindness
has made you his debtor!"
If, however, the benefactor has lapsed from virtue, nevertheless he
should be repaid according to his state, that he may return to virtue if
possible. But if he be so wicked as to be incurable, then his heart has
changed, and consequently no repayment is due for his kindness, as
heretofore. And yet, as far as it possible without sin, the kindness he
has shown should be held in memory, as the Philosopher says (Ethic. ix,
3).
Reply to Objection 6: As stated in the preceding reply, repayment of a favor
depends chiefly on the affection of the heart: wherefore repayment should
be made in such a way as to prove most beneficial. If, however, through
the benefactor's carelessness it prove detrimental to him, this is not
imputed to the person who repays him, as Seneca observes (De Benef. vii):
"It is my duty to repay, and not to keep back and safeguard my repayment."
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 106 [<< | >>]
Article: 4 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It seems that a man is bound to repay a favor at once. For we are
bound to restore at once what we owe, unless the term be fixed. Now there
is no term prescribed for the repayment of favors, and yet this repayment
is a duty, as stated above (Article [3]). Therefore a man is bound to repay a
favor at once.
Objection 2: Further, a good action would seem to be all the more praiseworthy
according as it is done with greater earnestness. Now earnestness seems
to make a man do his duty without any delay. Therefore it is apparently
more praiseworthy to repay a favor at once.
Objection 3: Further, Seneca says (De Benef. ii) that "it is proper to a
benefactor to act freely and quickly." Now repayment ought to equal the
favor received. Therefore it should be done at once.
On the contrary, Seneca says (De Benef. iv): "He that hastens to repay,
is animated with a sense, not of gratitude but of indebtedness."
I answer that, Just as in conferring a favor two things are to be
considered, namely, the affection of the heart and the gift, so also must
these things be considered in repaying the favor. As regards the
affection of the heart, repayment should be made at once, wherefore
Seneca says (De Benef. ii): "Do you wish to repay a favor? Receive it
graciously." As regards the gift, one ought to wait until such a time as
will be convenient to the benefactor. In fact, if instead of choosing a
convenient time, one wished to repay at once, favor for favor, it would
not seem to be a virtuous, but a constrained repayment. For, as Seneca
observes (De Benef. iv), "he that wishes to repay too soon, is an
unwilling debtor, and an unwilling debtor is ungrateful."
Reply to Objection 1: A legal debt must be paid at once, else the equality of
justice would not be preserved, if one kept another's property without
his consent. But a moral debt depends on the equity of the debtor: and
therefore it should be repaid in due time according as the rectitude of
virtue demands.
Reply to Objection 2: Earnestness of the will is not virtuous unless it be
regulated by reason; wherefore it is not praiseworthy to forestall the
proper time through earnestness.
Reply to Objection 3: Favors also should be conferred at a convenient time and
one should no longer delay when the convenient time comes; and the same
is to be observed in repaying favors.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 106 [<< | >>]
Article: 5 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It seems that in repaying favors we should not look at the
benefactor's disposition but at the deed. For repayment is due to
beneficence, and beneficence consists in deeds, as the word itself
denotes. Therefore in repaying favors we should look at the deed.
Objection 2: Further, thanksgiving, whereby we repay favors, is a part of
justice. But justice considers equality between giving and taking.
Therefore also in repaying favors we should consider the deed rather than
the disposition of the benefactor.
Objection 3: Further, no one can consider what he does not know. Now God alone
knows the interior disposition. Therefore it is impossible to repay a
favor according to the benefactor's disposition.
On the contrary, Seneca says (De Benef. i): "We are sometimes under a
greater obligation to one who has given little with a large heart, and
has bestowed a small favor, yet willingly."
I answer that, The repayment of a favor may belong to three virtues,
namely, justice, gratitude and friendship. It belongs to justice when the
repayment has the character of a legal debt, as in a loan and the like:
and in such cases repayment must be made according to the quantity
received.
On the other hand, repayment of a favor belongs, though in different
ways, to friendship and likewise to the virtue of gratitude when it has
the character of a moral debt. For in the repayment of friendship we have
to consider the cause of friendship; so that in the friendship that is
based on the useful, repayment should be made according to the usefulness
accruing from the favor conferred, and in the friendship based on virtue
repayment should be made with regard for the choice or disposition of the
giver, since this is the chief requisite of virtue, as stated in Ethic.
viii, 13. And likewise, since gratitude regards the favor inasmuch as it
is bestowed gratis, and this regards the disposition of the giver, it
follows again that repayment of a favor depends more on the disposition
of the giver than on the effect.
Reply to Objection 1: Every moral act depends on the will. Hence a kindly action,
in so far as it is praiseworthy and is deserving of gratitude, consists
materially in the thing done, but formally and chiefly in the will. Hence
Seneca says (De Benef. i): "A kindly action consists not in deed or gift,
but in the disposition of the giver or doer."
Reply to Objection 2: Gratitude is a part of justice, not indeed as a species is
part of a genus, but by a kind of reduction to the genus of justice, as
stated above (Question [80]). Hence it does not follow that we shall find the
same kind of debt in both virtues.
Reply to Objection 3: God alone sees man's disposition in itself: but in so far
as it is shown by certain signs, man also can know it. It is thus that a
benefactor's disposition is known by the way in which he does the kindly
action, for instance through his doing it joyfully and readily.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 106 [<< | >>]
Article: 6 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It seems that there is no need for the repayment of gratitude to
surpass the favor received. For it is not possible to make even equal
repayment to some, for instance, one's parents, as the Philosopher states
(Ethic. viii, 14). Now virtue does not attempt the impossible. Therefore
gratitude for a favor does not tend to something yet greater.
Objection 2: Further, if one person repays another more than he has received
by his favor, by that very fact he gives him something his turn, as it
were. But the latter owes him repayment for the favor which in his turn
the former has conferred on him. Therefore he that first conferred a
favor will be bound to a yet greater repayment, and so on indefinitely.
Now virtue does not strive at the indefinite, since "the indefinite
removes the nature of good" (Metaph. ii, text. 8). Therefore repayment of
gratitude should not surpass the favor received.
Objection 3: Further, justice consists in equality. But "more" is excess of
equality. Since therefore excess is sinful in every virtue, it seems that
to repay more than the favor received is sinful and opposed to justice.
On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. v, 5): "We should repay
those who are gracious to us, by being gracious to them return," and this
is done by repaying more than we have received. Therefore gratitude
should incline to do something greater.
I answer that, As stated above (Article [5]), gratitude regards the favor
received according the intention of the benefactor; who seems be
deserving of praise, chiefly for having conferred the favor gratis
without being bound to do so. Wherefore the beneficiary is under a moral
obligation to bestow something gratis in return. Now he does not seem to
bestow something gratis, unless he exceeds the quantity of the favor
received: because so long as he repays less or an equivalent, he would
seem to do nothing gratis, but only to return what he has received.
Therefore gratitude always inclines, as far as possible, to pay back
something more.
Reply to Objection 1: As stated above (Article [3], ad 5; Article [5]), in repaying favors we
must consider the disposition rather than the deed. Accordingly, if we
consider the effect of beneficence, which a son receives from his parents
namely, to be and to live, the son cannot make an equal repayment, as the
Philosopher states (Ethic. viii, 14). But if we consider the will of the
giver and of the repayer, then it is possible for the son to pay back
something greater to his father, as Seneca declares (De Benef. iii). If,
however, he were unable to do so, the will to pay back would be
sufficient for gratitude.
Reply to Objection 2: The debt of gratitude flows from charity, which the more it
is paid the more it is due, according to Rm. 13:8, "Owe no man anything,
but to love one another." Wherefore it is not unreasonable if the
obligation of gratitude has no limit.
Reply to Objection 3: As in injustice, which is a cardinal virtue, we consider
equality of things, so in gratitude we consider equality of wills. For
while on the one hand the benefactor of his own free-will gave something
he was not bound to give, so on the other hand the beneficiary repays
something over and above what he has received.