Index [<< | >>]
First Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 110 [<< | >>]
We must now consider the grace of God as regards its essence; and under
this head there are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether grace implies something in the soul?
(2) Whether grace is a quality?
(3) Whether grace differs from infused virtue?
(4) Of the subject of grace.
Index [<< | >>]
First Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 110 [<< | >>]
Article: 1 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that grace does not imply anything in the soul. For
man is said to have the grace of God even as the grace of man. Hence it
is written (Gn. 39:21) that the Lord gave to Joseph "grace [Douay:
'favor'] in the sight of the chief keeper of the prison." Now when we say
that a man has the favor of another, nothing is implied in him who has
the favor of the other, but an acceptance is implied in him whose favor
he has. Hence when we say that a man has the grace of God, nothing is
implied in his soul; but we merely signify the Divine acceptance.
Objection 2: Further, as the soul quickens the body so does God quicken the
soul; hence it is written (Dt. 30:20): "He is thy life." Now the soul
quickens the body immediately. Therefore nothing can come as a medium
between God and the soul. Hence grace implies nothing created in the soul.
Objection 3: Further, on Rm. 1:7, "Grace to you and peace," the gloss says:
"Grace, i.e. the remission of sins." Now the remission of sin implies
nothing in the soul, but only in God, Who does not impute the sin,
according to Ps. 31:2: "Blessed is the man to whom the Lord hath not
imputed sin." Hence neither does grace imply anything in the soul.
On the contrary, Light implies something in what is enlightened. But
grace is a light of the soul; hence Augustine says (De Natura et Gratia
xxii): "The light of truth rightly deserts the prevaricator of the law,
and those who have been thus deserted become blind." Therefore grace
implies something in the soul.
I answer that, According to the common manner of speech, grace is
usually taken in three ways. First, for anyone's love, as we are
accustomed to say that the soldier is in the good graces of the king,
i.e. the king looks on him with favor. Secondly, it is taken for any gift
freely bestowed, as we are accustomed to say: I do you this act of grace.
Thirdly, it is taken for the recompense of a gift given "gratis,"
inasmuch as we are said to be "grateful" for benefits. Of these three the
second depends on the first, since one bestows something on another
"gratis" from the love wherewith he receives him into his good "graces."
And from the second proceeds the third, since from benefits bestowed
"gratis" arises "gratitude."
Now as regards the last two, it is clear that grace implies something in
him who receives grace: first, the gift given gratis; secondly, the
acknowledgment of the gift. But as regards the first, a difference must
be noted between the grace of God and the grace of man; for since the
creature's good springs from the Divine will, some good in the creature
flows from God's love, whereby He wishes the good of the creature. On the
other hand, the will of man is moved by the good pre-existing in things;
and hence man's love does not wholly cause the good of the thing, but
pre-supposes it either in part or wholly. Therefore it is clear that
every love of God is followed at some time by a good caused in the
creature, but not co-eternal with the eternal love. And according to this
difference of good the love of God to the creature is looked at
differently. For one is common, whereby He loves "all things that are"
(Wis. 11:25), and thereby gives things their natural being. But the
second is a special love, whereby He draws the rational creature above
the condition of its nature to a participation of the Divine good; and
according to this love He is said to love anyone simply, since it is by
this love that God simply wishes the eternal good, which is Himself, for
the creature.
Accordingly when a man is said to have the grace of God, there is
signified something bestowed on man by God. Nevertheless the grace of God
sometimes signifies God's eternal love, as we say the grace of
predestination, inasmuch as God gratuitously and not from merits
predestines or elects some; for it is written (Eph. 1:5): "He hath
predestinated us into the adoption of children . . . unto the praise of
the glory of His grace."
Reply to Objection 1: Even when a man is said to be in another's good graces, it
is understood that there is something in him pleasing to the other; even
as anyone is said to have God's grace---with this difference, that what
is pleasing to a man in another is presupposed to his love, but whatever
is pleasing to God in a man is caused by the Divine love, as was said
above.
Reply to Objection 2: God is the life of the soul after the manner of an
efficient cause; but the soul is the life of the body after the manner of
a formal cause. Now there is no medium between form and matter, since the
form, of itself, "informs" the matter or subject; whereas the agent
"informs" the subject, not by its substance, but by the form, which it
causes in the matter.
Reply to Objection 3: Augustine says (Retract. i, 25): "When I said that grace
was for the remission of sins, and peace for our reconciliation with God,
you must not take it to mean that peace and reconciliation do not pertain
to general peace, but that the special name of grace signifies the
remission of sins." Not only grace, therefore, but many other of God's
gifts pertain to grace. And hence the remission of sins does not take
place without some effect divinely caused in us, as will appear later
(Question [113], Article [2]).
Index [<< | >>]
First Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 110 [<< | >>]
Article: 2 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that grace is not a quality of the soul. For no
quality acts on its subject, since the action of a quality is not without
the action of its subject, and thus the subject would necessarily act
upon itself. But grace acts upon the soul, by justifying it. Therefore
grace is not a quality.
Objection 2: Furthermore, substance is nobler than quality. But grace is
nobler than the nature of the soul, since we can do many things by grace,
to which nature is not equal, as stated above (Question [109], Articles [1],2,3).
Therefore grace is not a quality.
Objection 3: Furthermore, no quality remains after it has ceased to be in its
subject. But grace remains; since it is not corrupted, for thus it would
be reduced to nothing, since it was created from nothing; hence it is
called a "new creature"(Gal. 6:15).
On the contrary, on Ps. 103:15: "That he may make the face cheerful with
oil"; the gloss says: "Grace is a certain beauty of soul, which wins the
Divine love." But beauty of soul is a quality, even as beauty of body.
Therefore grace is a quality.
I answer that, As stated above (Article [1]), there is understood to be an
effect of God's gratuitous will in whoever is said to have God's grace.
Now it was stated (Question [109], Article [1]) that man is aided by God's gratuitous
will in two ways: first, inasmuch as man's soul is moved by God to know
or will or do something, and in this way the gratuitous effect in man is
not a quality, but a movement of the soul; for "motion is the act of the
mover in the moved." Secondly, man is helped by God's gratuitous will,
inasmuch as a habitual gift is infused by God into the soul; and for this
reason, that it is not fitting that God should provide less for those He
loves, that they may acquire supernatural good, than for creatures, whom
He loves that they may acquire natural good. Now He so provides for
natural creatures, that not merely does He move them to their natural
acts, but He bestows upon them certain forms and powers, which are the
principles of acts, in order that they may of themselves be inclined to
these movements, and thus the movements whereby they are moved by God
become natural and easy to creatures, according to Wis. 8:1: "she . . .
ordereth all things sweetly." Much more therefore does He infuse into
such as He moves towards the acquisition of supernatural good, certain
forms or supernatural qualities, whereby they may be moved by Him sweetly
and promptly to acquire eternal good; and thus the gift of grace is a
quality.
Reply to Objection 1: Grace, as a quality, is said to act upon the soul, not
after the manner of an efficient cause, but after the manner of a formal
cause, as whiteness makes a thing white, and justice, just.
Reply to Objection 2: Every substance is either the nature of the thing whereof
it is the substance or is a part of the nature, even as matter and form
are called substance. And because grace is above human nature, it cannot
be a substance or a substantial form, but is an accidental form of the
soul. Now what is substantially in God, becomes accidental in the soul
participating the Divine goodness, as is clear in the case of knowledge.
And thus because the soul participates in the Divine goodness
imperfectly, the participation of the Divine goodness, which is grace,
has its being in the soul in a less perfect way than the soul subsists in
itself. Nevertheless, inasmuch as it is the expression or participation
of the Divine goodness, it is nobler than the nature of the soul, though
not in its mode of being.
Reply to Objection 3: As Boethius [*Pseudo-Bede, Sent. Phil. ex Artist] says, the
"being of an accident is to inhere." Hence no accident is called being as
if it had being, but because by it something is; hence it is said to
belong to a being rather to be a being (Metaph. vii, text. 2). And
because to become and to be corrupted belong to what is, properly
speaking, no accident comes into being or is corrupted, but is said to
come into being and to be corrupted inasmuch as its subject begins or
ceases to be in act with this accident. And thus grace is said to be
created inasmuch as men are created with reference to it, i.e. are given
a new being out of nothing, i.e. not from merits, according to Eph. 2:10,
"created in Jesus Christ in good works."
Index [<< | >>]
First Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 110 [<< | >>]
Article: 3 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that grace is the same as virtue. For Augustine
says (De Spir. et Lit. xiv) that "operating grace is faith that worketh
by charity." But faith that worketh by charity is a virtue. Therefore
grace is a virtue.
Objection 2: Further, what fits the definition, fits the defined. But the
definitions of virtue given by saints and philosophers fit grace, since
"it makes its subject good, and his work good," and "it is a good quality
of the mind, whereby we live righteously," etc. Therefore grace is virtue.
Objection 3: Further, grace is a quality. Now it is clearly not in the
"fourth" species of quality; viz. "form" which is the "abiding figure of
things," since it does not belong to bodies. Nor is it in the "third,"
since it is not a "passion nor a passion-like quality," which is in the
sensitive part of the soul, as is proved in Physic. viii; and grace is
principally in the mind. Nor is it in the "second" species, which is
"natural power" or "impotence"; since grace is above nature and does not
regard good and evil, as does natural power. Therefore it must be in the
"first" species which is "habit" or "disposition." Now habits of the mind
are virtues; since even knowledge itself is a virtue after a manner, as
stated above (Question [57], Articles [1],2). Therefore grace is the same as virtue.
On the contrary, If grace is a virtue, it would seem before all to be
one of the three theological virtues. But grace is neither faith nor
hope, for these can be without sanctifying grace. Nor is it charity,
since "grace foreruns charity," as Augustine says in his book on the
Predestination of the Saints (De Dono Persev. xvi). Therefore grace is
not virtue.
I answer that, Some held that grace and virtue were identical in
essence, and differed only logically---in the sense that we speak of
grace inasmuch as it makes man pleasing to God, or is given
gratuitously---and of virtue inasmuch as it empowers us to act rightly.
And the Master seems to have thought this (Sent. ii, D 27).
But if anyone rightly considers the nature of virtue, this cannot hold,
since, as the Philosopher says (Physic. vii, text. 17), "virtue is
disposition of what is perfect---and I call perfect what is disposed
according to its nature." Now from this it is clear that the virtue of a
thing has reference to some pre-existing nature, from the fact that
everything is disposed with reference to what befits its nature. But it
is manifest that the virtues acquired by human acts of which we spoke
above (Question [55], seqq.) are dispositions, whereby a man is fittingly
disposed with reference to the nature whereby he is a man; whereas
infused virtues dispose man in a higher manner and towards a higher end,
and consequently in relation to some higher nature, i.e. in relation to a
participation of the Divine Nature, according to 2 Pt. 1:4: "He hath
given us most great and most precious promises; that by these you may be
made partakers of the Divine Nature." And it is in respect of receiving
this nature that we are said to be born again sons of God.
And thus, even as the natural light of reason is something besides the
acquired virtues, which are ordained to this natural light, so also the
light of grace which is a participation of the Divine Nature is
something besides the infused virtues which are derived from and are
ordained to this light, hence the Apostle says (Eph. 5:8): "For you were
heretofore darkness, but now light in the Lord. Walk then as children of
the light." For as the acquired virtues enable a man to walk, in
accordance with the natural light of reason, so do the infused virtues
enable a man to walk as befits the light of grace.
Reply to Objection 1: Augustine calls "faith that worketh by charity" grace,
since the act of faith of him that worketh by charity is the first act by
which sanctifying grace is manifested.
Reply to Objection 2: Good is placed in the definition of virtue with reference
to its fitness with some pre-existing nature essential or participated.
Now good is not attributed to grace in this manner, but as to the root of
goodness in man, as stated above.
Reply to Objection 3: Grace is reduced to the first species of quality; and yet
it is not the same as virtue, but is a certain disposition which is
presupposed to the infused virtues, as their principle and root.
Index [<< | >>]
First Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 110 [<< | >>]
Article: 4 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that grace is not in the essence of the soul, as in
a subject, but in one of the powers. For Augustine says (Hypognosticon
iii [*Among the spurious works of St. Augustine]) that grace is related
to the will or to the free will "as a rider to his horse." Now the will
or the free will is a power, as stated above (FP, Question [83], Article [2]). Hence
grace is in a power of the soul, as in a subject.
Objection 2: Further, "Man's merit springs from grace" as Augustine says (De
Gratia et Lib. Arbit. vi). Now merit consists in acts, which proceed from
a power. Hence it seems that grace is a perfection of a power of the soul.
Objection 3: Further, if the essence of the soul is the proper subject of
grace, the soul, inasmuch as it has an essence, must be capable of grace.
But this is false; since it would follow that every soul would be capable
of grace. Therefore the essence of the soul is not the proper subject of
grace.
Objection 4: Further, the essence of the soul is prior to its powers. Now what
is prior may be understood without what is posterior. Hence it follows
that grace may be taken to be in the soul, although we suppose no part or
power of the soul---viz. neither the will, nor the intellect, nor
anything else; which is impossible.
On the contrary, By grace we are born again sons of God. But generation
terminates at the essence prior to the powers. Therefore grace is in the
soul's essence prior to being in the powers.
I answer that, This question depends on the preceding. For if grace is
the same as virtue, it must necessarily be in the powers of the soul as
in a subject; since the soul's powers are the proper subject of virtue,
as stated above (Question [56], Article [1]). But if grace differs from virtue, it
cannot be said that a power of the soul is the subject of grace, since
every perfection of the soul's powers has the nature of virtue, as stated
above (Question [55], Article [1]; Question [56], Article [1]). Hence it remains that grace, as it is
prior to virtue, has a subject prior to the powers of the soul, so that
it is in the essence of the soul. For as man in his intellective powers
participates in the Divine knowledge through the virtue of faith, and in
his power of will participates in the Divine love through the virtue of
charity, so also in the nature of the soul does he participate in the
Divine Nature, after the manner of a likeness, through a certain
regeneration or re-creation.
Reply to Objection 1: As from the essence of the soul flows its powers, which are
the principles of deeds, so likewise the virtues, whereby the powers are
moved to act, flow into the powers of the soul from grace. And thus grace
is compared to the will as the mover to the moved, which is the same
comparison as that of a horseman to the horse---but not as an accident to
a subject.
And thereby is made clear the Reply to the Second Objection. For grace
is the principle of meritorious works through the medium of virtues, as
the essence of the soul is the principal of vital deeds through the
medium of the powers.
Reply to Objection 3: The soul is the subject of grace, as being in the species
of intellectual or rational nature. But the soul is not classed in a
species by any of its powers, since the powers are natural properties of
the soul following upon the species. Hence the soul differs specifically
in its essence from other souls, viz. of dumb animals, and of plants.
Consequently it does not follow that, if the essence of the human soul is
the subject of grace, every soul may be the subject of grace; since it
belongs to the essence of the soul, inasmuch as it is of such a species.
Reply to Objection 4: Since the powers of the soul are natural properties
following upon the species, the soul cannot be without them. Yet, granted
that it was without them, the soul would still be called intellectual or
rational in its species, not that it would actually have these powers,
but on account of the essence of such a species, from which these powers
naturally flow.