These may be summed up in: (1) The consent of all people (G. Roskoff, Das Religionswesen der rohesten Ndturvolker, Leipsic, 1880; O. F. Peschel, Volkerkunde, Leipsic, 1875; Bastian, Beiträge zur vergleichenden Psychologie, Berlin, 1868). (2) Proofs ab utili and a tutiori. The former conceives of the maintenance of the dogma of immortality as in the interest of public morals; the latter treats the theoretical uncertainty as if it were true for the sake of its benefit in this life. (3) The teleological proof. In the destination of the personal individual for perfection is found a means for the completion in a future world of the aim only partly attained here (J. H. Fichte, Idee der Peraonlichkeit und der individuuellen Fortdduer, Leipsic, 1855). (4) The analogical proof. The analogy of metamorphosis (the chrysalis, the sleep of winter, the seed-corn). (5) The astronomical proof is founded on the existence of a multitude of otherwise aimless heavenly bodies, and on the probability that even the particular life of each star is for the sake of enriching human knowledge. (6) The moral proof. According to Kant, the aim of life is the furthering of holiness as complete conformity to moral law; this becomes the postulate of an infinite progress. (7) Proof from the idea of righteousness. Virtue must be rewarded, sin punished, and since both are imperfectly realized here, another sphere of life is required (Athenagoms, Justin, Socinians, Arminians, Rationalists, Calvin Leibnitz). On ~ the other hand, the Stoics and
461 |
Clement of Alexandria (Stromata, IV., vi. 22) emphasized the immanent righteousness which strikes even the wicked in this world. Spinoza holds that although duty is filled with an infinite content, it does not need to be capped with an endless existence (Ethics, v. 41-42). Hant's moral proof, combined with the Christian estimate of life; has lost none of its validity. (8) Metaphysical proof, derived from the simplicity or the immateriality of the soul. From the mere heterogeneity of the spirit, one could infer (a) with Epicurus indifference to being or not being: " while we exist, death is not present; when death is present, we do not exist" (Diogenes Laertius, x. 27) or (b) an extension of immortality to animals. (9) . Ontological. On the ground of a genetic development in language and psychology, one may make use of a metaphysical inference which, in harmony with the total rational view of the world, proves the certainty of the final triumph of life over death, from the immanent eternity of the spirit already manifested in the ethical religious conquest of death (cf. Plato's play on words in the Pbmdo: the soul (a) life, accordingly "not-death," hence (b) " not-dead "-a-thanatoe).
V. The Original Motives: The original motives of belief in immortality correspond to the natural causes of the idea of God, which may be psychologically traced to a fourfold root. (1) Subjective: wish, fear of death, and hope of life. tuod volumus, credimus. Feuerbach: " Man thinks of his god as of his heaven. . . God and immortality are identical. Both originate in the wish" (cf. Ri9veda, x. 14, 8). According to the Talmud, Paradise is a place of bliss which, surpasses the joy of the Messianic time. " The pious are satisfied with the flesh (of the Leviathan) which was preserved for this end since the first day of creation, and they drink wine from clusters which were prepared since the bringing in of the world " (Wilnaehe, Die Vorstellungen vmn Zustonde nach dem Tode each Apokryphen, Talmud uttd Kirchenvaxern, in JPT, 1880, p. 449). On the other hand, the wish for reunion with the dead often yields to fear of the dead and to the desire not to be disturbed by them (cf. the words at the obsequies of Bodo in northeast India: "Take and eat; formerly hast thou eaten and drunken with us, but now thou canat no more; thou Overt one of us, thou art so no more; we come no more to thee, and come not thou nearer to us "). Like the funeral pyre, the funeral meals often celebrate only the separation as a symbolic agreement with the dead. (2) The influence of striking experiences in dreams on the imagination and the view of the world is noteworthy in the lower stages of culture (see!COMPARATIVZ RELIGION, III., vi., 1 2; and cf. E. B. Tylor, Primitive Culture, vol. i., London, 1871). The New Zealander thinks that the dreaming soul departs from the body and returns again after wandering in the realm of the dead and there communing with its friends. The land of the blessed reflects the popular ideals. The dreaming Indian visits his hunting-ground, the Greek beholds the Elysian fields, the German thought that life in Walhalla consisted of bloody battles. Still more significant are the associations of ideas by which the character of a dream is attributed to the earthly
life-life a dream; death the moment in which one
awakes from the dream of life to its true reality.
The Old Testament increasingly discredits the prophetic dream (cf. Deut. xiii.; Jer. xxiii.; Eool. v.
2-6).
Yet the actual present is designated as a
"being like those who dream" in relation to a
higher form of existence (Ps. exxvi. 1). (3) In the
lower stages of culture the intellectual riddle of
death leads to the idea of a brief extension of life
beyond the grave. After death there is to be a
separation which either completes the death or
prepares for a further lifetime in other regions
(so the Fijis, the Guinea negroes, the Greenlanders);
or only the chief men continued to exist (so the
Tonga Islanders), or only the souls of the good (so
the Nicaraguans). The funeral-pyre may condition
the continued existence of the dead. For the enduring connection between soul and body, cf.
Odyssey, xi. 51
sqq.,
73; Iliad. xxiii. 71
sqq.; Vergil,
Xneid, vi. 325
sqq., 362 sqq.;
462 |
VI. The Principal Elements of the Christian Ideal
of Immortality: The Christian estimate of life subordinates all motives of the hope of immortality to
belief in God; he is " not the God of the dead, but
of the living." Presuppositions for correct deduction are: (1) Negatively: proof maynot be adduced
from rational psychology. If the soul of man is
immortal because it is simple and immaterial, the
same must be true of animals and of plants: these
no less than the soul of man may be regarded
sub
specie o=tewnitatis.
Moreover, the thought of immortality is developed from simple psychical experiences. The child lives in the joy of the unending
moment. Many savages have need only to project
thought forward for a year or a month; the abstract
idea of immortality matures first with monotheism.
Even then "absolute endlessness" remains only a
half-understood problem. The question of immortality retires to the background in comparison
with the ethical social interests and with faith in
God in which the true endlessness is felt (Ps. lxxiii.).
If with Berkeley, Fichte, and Schopenhauer one
conceives the idea not as result, but as cause of the
entire world, including time and apace, then the
thinking subject as thinking can not be destroyed
by the object which it has itself produced-time.
The notions of subject, object, idea, time, infinite,
and the like are not original; still more elementary
is language, which originates in a practical motive.
(2) Positively; the verbal condition of the solution
of the problem. (a) Soul is the man as a unity;
body is the man as an organism of many factors.
The word "soul" in popular use is associated with
the idea of the sea in motion. In the notion of soul
lies life, change, inconstancy, death. The nature
of
psychg is
perishableness. Even knowledge will
not shield from destruction
(
earth been developed through ethical growth,
suffering, and victory (cf.
VII. The Truth of These Forms of Experience: In the degree to which the naturally true and ethically grounded idea creates a corresponding expression can the truth of its affirmation be removed from doubt. This is proved by the religion of Buddhism. Although one may never say that the soul is or is not in Nirvdna, yet this is designated as the " land of peace," the " immeasurable, abysmal sea of eternity." Even to a philosopher such experiences compel the thought of a positive, ideal imperishableness. Mightier than with the Buddhist is the Christian's longing for absolute emancipation and blessedness. The fulness of God's love, as it fills the Christian heart absorbed in the kingdom of God, is immediately infinite. In the degree to which there is given the real basis for an idea true to life must the positive joy in the picture of the Christian hope of glory be affirmed.
In conclusion, the attitude toward immortality will be positive in case (1) the certainty of God as the supreme concrete content of the consciousness is presupposed, (2) the one miracle which lies in the being of the entire world is beheld under the correct figure of a creative divine deed, and accordingly (3) the hope of the future which corresponds to the Christian valuation of life is directly related to the. idea of the creative divine deed. The twofold contents of the Christian spirit of life are (1) the idea of the Father-God as the free creative love, and (2) the hope that nothing hereafter can separate from the "infinite" worth of the love of God. If the real grounds of both of these ideas are inexhaustible, then the endeavors after a formal presentation of faith in God and immortality must be just as enduring as the power of language (see also Eschatology).
For extended discussion and proof of this thesis cf. G. Runze, Btudien zur wgleicAenden Religions wasaenschaft; II., Die Psychologie des Ur:sterblich keitSglaubens und der Unsterblichkeitaleugnung, Ber lin, 1894. G. RuNzE.
VIII. Additional Note: The arguments from data
furnished by the Society of Psychical Research, to
the effect that authentic messages have been received from those who have passed from the earthly
life, lack convincing cogency (cf. F. W. H. Myers,
Human Personality,
London, 1903). Not to accentuate the still incomplete evidence for the alleged
communications, this, if valid, would at best prove
only that some who have ceased to live here continue their life in other conditions. But whether
this is true for all, or whether any or all of those
who have been supposed to manifest themselves
from the other world will live forever does not yet
appear. The Biblical evidence for the immortality,
i.e., the resurrection, of all, including the wicked,
is not perhaps decisive. This involves the critical
interpretation of three passages which are open to
other values than those which have been assigned
to them
(
463 |
ptian of Immortality, Boston, 1900). Since all life is controlled by ends that attract and yet are hidden, and man does not fully reach these ends in this world, and can progressively attain them, if at all, only in an endless advance, his very incompleteness is his mightiest witness to immortality. For the perplexing problem of the relation of personal
identity and memory to the life after death, of. H. Mtunsterberg, The Eternal Life (Boston, 1905). The most important recent literature bearing on this subject is the series of Ingersoll Lectures on Immortality given annually at Harvard University as follows: G. A. Gordon, Immortality and the Neto Theodicy, Boston, 1897; W. James, Human Immortality, Boston, 1898; B. I. Wheeler, Dionysius and Immortality, Boston, 1899; J. Royce, Conception of Immortality, Boston, 1900; J. Fiske, Life Everlasting, Boston, 1901; W. Osler, Science and Immortality, Boston, 1904; S. M. Crothers, The Endless Life, Boston, 1905; H. Milnsterberg,, The Eternal Life, Boston, 1905; C. F. Dole, Hope of Immortality, New York, 1906; W. Ostwald, Individuality and Immortality, Boston, 1906; W. S. Bigelow, Bud dhism and Immortality, Boston, 1908.
Bibliography: The earlier literature in wonderfully complete and classified form is in E. Abbot,' The Literature of the Doctrine of a Future Life, included in W. R. Alger's Destiny of the Bout, a Critical History of the Doctrine of a Future Life, Boston, 1880; cf. J. H. Hurst, Literature of Theology, pp. 496-497, New York, 1896. For the Biblical belief, besides the O. T. Theology 'of H. Schultz, London, 1892, and the N. T. Theology of W. Beyxhleg, Edinburgh, 1896, consult: J. Challis, An Essay on the Scripture Doctrine of Immortality, London, 1880: F. Schwally, Das Leban n ach deft Tode nach den Voretetlungen des alten Israel and des Judenthums, Giessen, 1892; A. Chambers, Ow Life q/tw Death: or, the Teaching of the Bible con cerning the Unseen World, London, 1894; J. Frey, Tod, Seaknglaubs and Swlsnkuu i m alfrn larast, Leipsic, 1898; L. A. Muirhead. The Terms Life and Death in the old and New Testament, Glasgow, 1908.
On the general subject, besides the works named in the text, consult: H. Schultz, Die Voraueastmngen der christ lichen Lshre von der Unsferbliehkei4 G Sttingen, 1861; A. lmmer, Der Uneterbliahkoeuglaube i m Lwhte der Geschichte und d er peoerewdrtiqen Wiwmaehaf4 Bern, 1868; R. S. Candlish, Life in a Risen Savior; an Exposition of .
1 Cor. xv., London, 1883; K. wilmarehof, Due jenseus, tin wissenechafelicher Versuch sur LGeung der UnsterbliChkeiitafrage, Leipsic 18&3-66; L. Figuier, The To-morrow of Deal,% or, the Future Life according to SeiencA Boston, 1872; T. A. Goodwin, The Mode of Man's Immortality, New York, 1874; A. B. Blackwell, Physical Basis of Immortality, New York, 1876; B. Stewart and P. G. Teat, The Unssen Universe, London, 1876 (from the standpoint of physical science); J. W. Rinck, Vom Zudandt der Seele nach deft Tode. Basel, 1878; G. Teichmilller, Ueber die Unetarblirhkeft der Seele, Leipsic, 1879 W. R. Hart, Eternal Purpose; a Study in the Scripture Doctrine of Immortality, Philadelphia, 1882; G. A. Gordon, The Witness to Immortality in Literature, Philosophy' and Life, Boston, 1883; L. Schneider, Die Unetwbiichkeitaidet i m Olauben und der Philosophic der Vdlker, Reganeburg, 1883; E. Neville, La Vic ltermlle Paris, 1884; E. Petavel-Ollif, Le Probalme de limmortolitE, 2 vols., Lausanne, 1891-92, Eng. transl., The Problem of Immortality, New York. 1893; A. Sabstier, Essai cur l'immortalitt au point de vue du naturalisme 6rolutioniete, Paris, 1895; E. Rohde, Psyche, Freiburg. 1898 (a classic; dels with Greek and Roman ideas); V. L. Bernier, SpirituadiM et immortalitd, Le Chapelle-Montligeon, 1901; H. Cremer, Ueber don Zustand reach deft Tede, Gütersloh, 1901; S. D. F. Seamond, The Christian Doctrine of Immortality, Edinburgh, 1901; w. Schneider, Due andere Leben, Paderborn, 1902; A. Chambers, Our Life after Death, London, 1903; W. Chest, Immortality a Rational Faith, New York, 1903; G. T. Feohner. Barhtein von den Leben reach den. Tode, Hamburg, 1903; C. W. Leadbmter, The Other Side q/ Death S eienfiftcouy Examined, Chicago, 1903; H. A. A. Kennedy, St. Paul's Conarptiane of the Last Things, London, 1904; L, Elb6. La Vie future, Paris, 1906; J. H. Hyslop, Science and a Future Life, London, 1906; K. Andersen, Die Vnetarbliehkeifafrape, Leipsic, 1906; G. Fell. Immortality of do Human Soul Philosophically Explained, London, 1906; L. Elb6, Future Life in the Light of Ancient Wisdom and Modern Science, London,
464 |
Calvin College. Last modified on 08/11/06. Contact the CCEL. |